|
Macedo, Stephen. (2000).
Diversity and Distrust: Civic Education in a Multicultural
Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
384 pp.
$47.50 (cloth)
ISBN 0-674-21311-4
Michele S. Moses
Arizona State University
June 19, 2002
According to noted
political theorist, Stephen Macedo, "good citizens are not
simply born that way" (p. 16). Indeed not. And with
Diversity and Distrust: Civic Education in a Multicultural
Democracy, Macedo has provided us with a nuanced and detailed
look at what needs to be done in order to properly foster good
citizenship in a diverse liberal democratic society. This work
can be included in the best of recent democratic political
theory, most notably Amy Gutmann and Dennis Thompson's
Democracy and Disagreement: Why Moral Conflict Cannot Be
Avoided in Politics, and What Should Be Done about It
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1996).
Macedo divides the book
into three parts, which helps the reader follow the organization
of his thought on the subject. Part 1, "Public Schooling
and American Citizenship," provides a general history of
public schools in the United States, with a particular focus on
their role in fostering shared civic values. He includes a
notable analysis of the early relationship between Protestantism,
democracy, and the common school movement. Part 2,
"Liberal Civic Education and Religious
Fundamentalism," examines public schooling in light of
conflicts between its civic aims and parental and religious
rights. Here he provides detailed analyses of important court
cases dealing with the rights of deeply religious groups to opt
out of parts of public education, such as Mozert v.
Hawkins and Wisconsin v. Yoder. Though there is
nothing very new in what he says, the details he shares help to
give the reader a good context from which to understand his many
arguments. His aim is to shed light on how these deep-seated
conflicts ought to be handled. And, part 3, "School Reform
and Civic Education," discusses how school reform might be
refocused so as to support civic educational aims more
strongly.
Reading Diversity and
Distrust is an experience in reasonableness. So often
scholarship on issues as contentious as how to deal with
religious and moral diversity, what the primary purposes of
education should be, and how school reform ought to be
structured, devolves into shrill rhetoric, with no possible
compromise in sight. In Diversity and Distrust, Macedo
tells a story about America and its fragile democracy that places
civic ideals at the center of common life. Macedo puts forth the
compelling case that we should not take it for granted that our
civic aims will continue to be strongly promoted either through
the educational system or through other means.
Macedo follows in the
recent tradition of contemporary liberal political philosophers
such as Charles Taylor and Will Kymlicka, who, like Macedo, also
see the political theory of liberalism as necessarily not neutral
with respect to competing conceptions of the good life. Yet he
carves out his own particular brand of contemporary liberal
theory in the form of what he calls "civic
liberalism." The idea of a strong civic liberalism
provides the theoretical backbone for Macedo's arguments
about democracy, civic aims, diversity, and schooling.
Much like traditional
liberalism, Macedo's civic liberalism as an ideal political
system places freedom at center; yet it moves beyond an emphasis
on liberty alone to an emphasis on fostering good citizenship in
order to create a society that will support freedom in the long
run. Relying significantly on John Rawls' political
liberalism, civic liberalism entails that citizens learn to,
among other things, be tolerant of others, act responsibly,
participate in public affairs, and cooperate with others.
Macedo's project here is to discern just how to foster
civic liberalismhow to bring civic ideals to the
forefront of the liberal project. It seems like he is trying to
forge a middle ground between liberals concerned with honoring
diversity and particular identities, and those more concerned
with promoting societal unity and shared values.
As I mentioned above,
throughout the work, Macedo does an admirable job of avoiding
stridency. In so doing, he avoids simplifying the very complex
concepts he undertakes to analyze. His approach is a moderate
one, though this does not make his arguments any less forceful or
well considered. He gives equal time to criticism of those on
the Right of the political spectrum (e.g., John Chubb and Terry
Moe) and those on the Left (e.g., Iris Marion Young). Just as he
blasts traditional liberalism, he also criticizes postmodern
theory based on the politics of identity.
According to Macedo,
diversity has large value, but it should not always be the
paramount organizing virtue of our polity. The book deals mainly
with religious and moral diversity rather than the issues of
racial and ethnic diversity more often associated with
multiculturalism. Diversity is important, but in Macedo's
words, "needs to be kept in its place" (p. 3). Thus,
he writes, we should not accept it uncritically. Diversity needs
to be shaped so that it does not interfere with the demands of a
shared civic life.
He takes issue with
postmodern theories that uncritically embrace difference and
inclusion. After all, there are some groups whose beliefs and
values warrant their exclusion (i.e., those based on ignorance
and racism). He comments that "our current notion of
‘difference' is far too thin and devoid of moral
content to characterize what it takes to constitute the shared
life of a reasonably stable, peaceful, and mutually respectful
urban order" (p. 26). He warns of the slippery slope
inherent in the postmodern desire to grant equal standing to
different views of the world. If equal legitimacy is granted,
how then, asks Macedo insightfully, can we rightfully call into
question Christian Identity worldviews that hold both Jewish
people and gay people to be evil?
A key to his argument
regarding the limits of diversity is the issue of religious
opposition to fundamental civic values. He believes that it is
"a profound mistake to identify religious seriousness with
illiberal religiosity" (p. 37). The central problem he
sees with an unconditional love of diversity as a value above all
others is that in the name of mutual respect, citizens owe each
other common and nonreligious reasons for shaping the shared
political morality needed for a stable democracy. If we are
misguided and starry-eyed about diversity and tolerance, then we
risk compromising common civic purposes.
As sensible as Macedo is
in crafting his theory, one weakness in the work is that he does
not properly attend to the historical reality of oppressive
Americanization efforts in the name of our shared civic values.
He mentions that immigrants have often been treated unfairly
within the educational system, yet he claims that "racist
antipathy was, for the vast majority of Americans, subordinated
to the hopeful conviction that with a proper education, immigrant
and native-born Americans could share a common citizenship"
(p. 63). His analysis of racism, power, and forced assimilation
is inadequate, though in his spirit of reasonableness, he does
helpfully remind us that there were complex reasons behind
assimilation efforts. Still, it seems as though Macedo wants to
somehow see assimilation as a good overall, despite what he calls
its "excesses" (p. 103). "Assimilation,"
he maintains, "is not to be despised; it is rather to be
embracedif we assimilate in nonoppressive ways and
toward justifiable values" (p. 146). The problem is that
in our stratified society, not everyone is included in deciding
whether or not the assimilation is indeed oppressive, whether or
not the values are justified. Oppression can and does occur when
people take "reasonable measures to secure the survival and
health of our liberal civic order," (p. 151) as Macedo
urges us to do.
Regarding the primary
aim of public education in a democracy, Macedo writes that
"liberal democratic public institutions count on shaping
wider social norms and expectations so that people are gently
encouraged to behave in ways that are broadly supportive of our
shared civic project" (p. x). In this book, Macedo does a
fine job of justifying that public institutions such as schools
ought to do just that; yet, it is curious that he does not
examine how we go about ensuring that such gentle encouragement
does not become coercive. The "shared civic project"
in the United States was conceived of and developed by white
Protestant men; white women, non-Protestants, and people of color
were largely excluded from shaping that project. Still, Macedo
insists that we believe in it and thus structure our school
system around the promotion of shared civic values.
Macedo is not an
educationist. His concern with education is due to its prominent
role in promoting civic aims. And as somewhat of an outsider to
debates over public school reform, he is able to point out that
in the rush to embrace market-based choice reforms, scant
attention has been paid to the educational aim of advancing civic
purposes. He argues that some would-be reformers are setting up
a false choice between the promotion of civic purposes in public
schools and religious freedom. Schools can be considerate and
tolerant of religious and moral diversity without giving up the
commitment to prepare a diverse group of students for
participation in a democratic society.
He is rightly skeptical
of market-based reform schemes that have as their putative
primary concern raising academic achievement (as measured by
standardized test scores). According to Macedo, any reforms that
take place should center on improving the quality of education,
especially civic education. But by placing the civic purposes of
public education prior to any other educational aims, Macedo
leaves aside other purposes, which are important in their own
right. For example, what of equal opportunity? Shouldn't
the top priority of public schools be to level students'
morally arbitrary starting places in life? Macedo fails to
contend with other prominent liberal theorists such as Ronald
Dworkin, who posit that equality, rather than liberty, should be
the core principle of our liberal democracy. Perhaps a deeper
consideration of equality would lead Macedo too far afloat from
his central project. It nonetheless remains an important facet
to the question of how to best deal with diversity.
All told, Macedo has
attempted to, in his words, "grapple with the hard
questions posed by the tensions between deep diversity and our
shared civic ideals in modern societies" (p. 109). He has
done so admirably. In fact, near the end of the book, Macedo
mentions his next projecta companion piece to this book
where he moves beyond public schools and examines the civic
imperatives of other political institutions. I await the
completion of his next project with anticipation. After reading
Diversity and Distrust, I trust that other readers will
feel the same.
Note
Reprinted with
permission from the American Journal of Education
(http://www.journals.uchicago.edu/AJE/home.html).
About the
Reviewer
Michele S.
Moses is Assistant
Professor of Educational Leadership and Policy Studies at Arizona
State University. She received her Ph.D. from the University of
Colorado at Boulder, specializing in the philosophy of education
and education policy analysis. She is the author of a new book,
Embracing Race: Why We Need Race-Conscious Education
Policy (Teachers College Press, 2002). Her research focuses
on issues of equality and social justice within education
policies related to multiculturalism and poverty.
| |