|
Levinson, Meira. (1999). The Demands of Liberal
Education. New York: Oxford University Press
Pp. vii + 237
$45.00 (Hard Cover) ISBN 0-190829544-8
$21.95 (Paperback) ISBN 0-19925044-8
Reviewed by Sarah M. McGough
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign
January 28, 2003
Oxford-trained liberal theorist and practicing
teacher, Meira Levinson, offers a well-articulated argument for
her vision of the ideal liberal education in The Demands of
Liberal Education. Particularly helpful for those of us who
struggle to convey the aims of liberal education to our children
and students, she provides an eloquent explanation as she
describes her ideal school and the steps necessary for its
realization:
The aim of liberal education is to teach
children the skills, habits, knowledge, and dispositions for them
to be thoughtful, mature, self-assured individuals who map their
path in the world with care and confidence, take responsibility
for their actions, fulfill their duties as citizens, question
themselves and others when appropriate, listen to and learn from
others, and ultimately lead their lives with dignity, integrity,
and self-respect—i.e. to be autonomous in the fullest sense
of the word (1999, p. 164).
As her words paint a portrait of an educated individual, we
can see that it is colored by autonomy, a central tenet
throughout her work.
Striving to fill the literature gap existing
between specialized writings on liberalism and the slew of
commentary on liberal civic education, Levinson sets out to
clarify the more general connection between contemporary
political theory and education policy. She endeavors to dispel
false intuitions about liberalism adopted by theorists and
practitioners as they shape education policy so that she can
make liberalism a more coherent theory with an integrated
understanding of education as essential to its success. This
stated intent made me a bit uncomfortable from the outset, for I
feared that she may focus too much on improving education as it
relates to strengthening liberalism, rather than giving
sufficient attention to improving education itself so that
liberal goals can be actualized in citizens. Though this doubt
lingered with me as I read, I began to see that, for Levinson,
these two goals should not and cannot be separated, for their
achievement is codependent.
Her first chapter begins with a methodical
defining of liberalism which may be of little interest to those
already familiar with the political theory, but eases newcomers
into her argument and acquaints them with its position in the
history of liberal talk. From the beginning, she explicitly
states that she will not defend liberalism and its principles,
which is an acceptable omission given that the topic of her book
already assumes their recognized importance. Other exclusions in
her initial defining of liberalism are not as acceptable,
however. Although she briefly justifies scholars who have
influenced her preferred understanding of contemporary liberalism
from a small list of well-knowns (Rawls, Locke, Hobbes, Mill,
and the like), she does not bother justifying that list as opposed to one
of more recent, perhaps lesser-knowns, who further or challenge
the liberal frameworks uttered by these men. Similarly, she
tends to simplify liberalism into a political/autonomy-based
divide. Surely liberalism is more nuanced than these
alternatives, such that one cannot be judged superior to the
other without being influenced by or paying respect to
third-party liberal voices or critics. Inclusion of these others
would make her portrayal of liberalism more accurately complex
and might make the liberalism she favors more convincing.
Nonetheless, she aptly defines the three elements
of contemporary liberal theory as (a) the fact of pluralism,
where there are many conceptions of the good life; (b) the
legitimation process, whereby free and equal citizens
consensually adopt governing principles and institutions; and (c)
substantive liberal institutions, which form a constitutional
democracy respective of individual liberties and conceptions of
the good life. As she rightly claims, liberals of varying types
struggle to unify these elements. Picking on political liberals
who are not as supportive of the centrality of autonomy as she
is, Levinson tries to show that political liberalism requires at
least a rudimentary level of autonomy in order for unification to
be achievable by way of justifying liberal freedoms and
institutions. She challenges Rawls and others from his political
camp by arguing against their claim that autonomy is just a
capacity. Instead, she asserts that it is a good that is a
necessary and central part of contemporary liberal theory. She
proposes that liberal freedoms and institutions are best grounded
in a weakly perfectionist sense of autonomy, which she initially
defines as the ability to form, evaluate, revise, and realize
one’s own conception of the good. An alternative to
political liberalism, Levinson defines a weakly perfectionist
state as one that “(1) values individual autonomy and
provides citizens the means and freedoms to exercise it; (2)
treats all responsible, self-authenticating individuals as equal
citizens; and therefore (3) does not discriminate against
non-autonomous citizens in protecting their rights or fulfilling
its obligation toward them” (p. 22). Her disagreement with
political liberalism, however, lingers throughout the book,
popping up here and there as she adopts some of its claims while
persistently trying to show the superiority of autonomy-based
weak perfectionism. Even after its initial overturn in this
first chapter, she brings it up repeatedly, just to shut it down,
seemingly beating a dead horse.
As she defends autonomy-valuing liberalism, she
tries to fashion a conception of autonomy that is substantive,
yet as minimal as possible, and with wide appeal. In the spirit
of her liberal predecessor, Eamonn Callan (1988), she points out
that autonomy is a word used by people in many different ways and
that philosophers cannot define it out of thin air to serve their
purposes. Appropriately, then, she attempts to define autonomy
without diverging too far from its commonly used sense of
“self-rule.” While this gives her project a grounded
feel and makes her argument comprehensible to the lay person, it
goes against her intent to shatter uncritical intuitions which
are widely held about liberalism. This should include
scrutinizing the common use of a liberal term such as autonomy
before adopting that use as pivotal to her seemingly more
thorough employment, Callan’s warning notwithstanding.
Insofar as her version of liberalism is committed
to the adult exercise of autonomy, Levinson believes liberalism
must be held to the corresponding commitment of developing
autonomy in future adults, i.e., children. She rightly
identifies necessary preconditions for autonomy in terms of first
achieving personhood. Autonomy requires personality which
enables one to be a choosing agent by virtue of having an
identity from which to begin considering alternatives. She
describes this in terms of “cultural coherence” in
that one’s culture provides the values and identities
necessary for one to identify one’s self. Being embedded
in a culture also allows a person to use the normative framework
of that culture to consider alternative lifestyles found
elsewhere. An individual’s autonomy is also dependent on a
plurality of constitutive values and beliefs. By aligning
one’s self with some values and not others, one is able to
have a standpoint from which to consider certain values one holds
as well as those of other’s without putting one’s
identity as a whole in jeopardy. They also allow an individual
to introspectively consider the criticisms others make of him or
her. Interestingly, the liberal “fact of plurality”
becomes quietly transformed into the “good of
plurality” as the book develops. It is a good because it
contributes to the good, autonomy, by requiring individuals to
defend their chosen conceptions of the good against a range of
others available to them. Sufficient justification for its
elevated status in her particular understanding of liberalism
seems lacking and its skewing effect on the three elements of
liberalism that she is trying to unify is overlooked. Moreover,
her differentiation between the existence of many, often
competing, conceptions of the good amongst peoples and the
existence of a variety of substantive values held by an
individual is problematically unclear.
To my delight, however, plurality as an
autonomy-promoting good is linked to an autonomy-promoting
community, for whose interest she argues that liberal freedoms
and institutions must be designed to protect. Hence, she moves
liberalism from its commonly known emphasis on individuals to its
lesser appreciated concern for communities, along the way
unveiling the tedious co-dependency of liberalism on a plural
public culture for its own survival. But while plural
communities provide the conditions for the exercise of autonomy,
schools offer the best space for its development. And it is to
this which she turns in chapter two. There, she provides a
lengthy paragraph which lists personal qualities needed for
developing and achieving autonomy. These range from clear
self-expression to imagination and from literacy to being
culturally socialized. While her sense of autonomy is admittedly
demanding and difficult to fully achieve, the characteristics she
lists are admirable and capable of being fulfilled in a
supportive context. Her sense of autonomy fits with the
idealistic spirit of the book and is reasoned enough to prevent
contenders from claiming it should be more simple.
The second chapter also argues that liberal theory
is compatible with state obligated coercion in the form of
paternalism, where the coherently defined liberal state has the
best understanding of the child’s interests, i.e., the
development of autonomy, in mind. Coercion with the intent of
such development is permissible because the capacity it fosters
can later be used to overcome future coercion. Coercion by
parents, however, is often problematically geared toward the
actualization of parents’ own particular, content-driven,
conceptions of the good improperly imposed on children who are
not yet capable of choosing the good for themselves. She tackles
parental rights claims to dictating the educational interests of
children well by explaining that the child’s interest in
the development of his or her own capacity for autonomy should be
privileged over the muscle-flexing exercise of parental
autonomy. She suitably uses the case of religious fundamentalist
children who are raised to be heteronymous and to uphold one
narrow view of the good life as an example of unjustified
parental control which limits the child’s development of
autonomy. She draws on James Dwyer briefly as she differentiates
parents’ privileges to guide children from mistaken claims
to parents’ rights to control them. It seems that more of
his work could provide empirical cases in which state-controlled
education for autonomy must make significant demands in order to
ensure the well-being and autonomy of its students. Expanding on
this distinction could also bolster her later discussion of
school choice.
Levinson contends that schools whose structure is
autonomy-oriented through their privileging of critical
reflection, reasoned argument, toleration, and other
self-legislating endeavors are locations where, when immersed,
children would most likely develop their own capacities. She
suggests the opposite of most liberals’ intuitions about
schooling, a school detached from the particular values and
commitments held by parents or democratically chosen by the local
community. In such a school, parental involvement would be
welcomed, but parental voices could not shape the aims and
content of the school. Levinson believes that this demand of
liberal education would free children from parental tyranny which
requires strict adherence to a particular conception of the good,
bringing them into a plural community of culturally imbedded
others where autonomy and defensible notions of the good life can
be fostered. Although respectful of the developmental
appropriateness of such activity, I fear she underestimates the
strain children may feel when torn between the visions of life
and education they receive from their state school and those
upheld at home, if they have a home life stable enough to pass
down a vision at all. Perhaps this is a negligible first
generation effect that would be overcome once those children,
schooled in the value of autonomy, themselves become parents.
Nonetheless, the pain for students in the present is certainly
hard to overlook. There is also another knotty future issue that
Levinson does not sufficiently address. Following a few
generations of schooling under her liberal educational ideal,
many now viable ways of life would no longer be tenable because
they would be in conflict with fully developed autonomy. This
loss is detrimental to rich pluralism and diversity, as fellow
liberal William Galston (1991; 2002) would most likely agree.
Levinson’s work is particularly interesting when read in
conjunction with William Galston’s latest release,
Liberal Pluralism (2002). The contradictions between the
two make the demands Levinson is articulating clearer and shed
light on their intensity. Galston argues against educational
policy like that advocated by Levinson which places the coercive
power of the state in the specific direction of upholding one
specific, autonomy-driven, view of the good life. He contends
that such an act violates the negative liberty of citizens.
Galston also disagrees with Levinson regarding parental rights.
With two key liberal commentators struggling over such a
monumental topic, the reading of both is worthwhile and
intriguing. Levinson would most likely contend that liberalism
is not about maximization of choices, but about fostering good
options which are in accord with liberal citizenship. This is a
hard sell to make to those who see narrowly defining the good
life in terms of autonomy as antithetical to liberalism itself.
Inclusion of her thorough response to this matter would make her
argument for implementation more robust.
Unlike many liberal commentators, Levinson gives
more than just a cursory nod to the arguments of
“deschoolers, functionalists, and other radical
theorists” (p. 82) regarding the hidden curriculum that
would most likely continue to operate in the detached school she
suggests. Instead of shrugging off their critique, she adopts
their insights, overtly including the hidden curriculum, though
renaming it the “informal curriculum”. She claims
that the open discussion of this aspect of schooling would be a
valuable, knowable, and recognizable lesson in her ideal school.
She hopes that it can be used to overcome
“autonomy-inhibiting, capitalist-driven education
reform” (p. 86) when explicitly used to unveil these
underpinnings typically functioning in schools.
She turns next to discussing civic education.
Though the transition feels a bit awkward, the topic’s
inclusion is necessary to making her portrayal of autonomy in a
weak perfectionist state more thorough and to position her work
amongst others who have recently considered civic education,
though typically (as in the case of Amy Gutmann) more narrowly
discussed in terms of democratic education. Levinson argues that
education for autonomy and education for citizenship are not only
compatible, but are also mutually reinforcing. Because civic
education ensures the maintenance of a healthy liberal state
which protects liberal freedoms and institutions, it is a
prerequisite for the exercising of autonomy which depends on
those very freedoms and institutions. There is also a
considerable overlap of the skills and habits needed for both.
She claims that civic education alerts students to their
liberties, showing them how and to what extent they may act on
them. She draws on the commonality of civic demands placed on
all political actors to argue that the ideal liberal school
should be common, with mutual language, common civic history, and
some shared values. Schools should be a place where the
private-public distinction of political liberalism is blurred
(though not relinquished) through the minimally discriminatory
incorporation of private commitments into the public identity
cultivated in the school. She analyzes the treatment of private
identities and public character within English, French, and
American schools as she reaches this conclusion. She also
contends that civic education offers a stable,
‘thick’ cultural identity which can be adopted by
those students who are unable to achieve embeddedness within the
culture of their private home. It also provides the necessary
shared and stable conditions for agency. This common identity
arising from civic education can in some ways resolve the
conflict between the development of choice and the development of
cultural coherence which lingers in her autonomy-driven
liberalism, though some may contend that is a homogenizing
solution.
The final chapter deals with some steps and
conditions necessary for the implementation of her ideal. One of
these is granting parents and children a controlled choice in
selecting which school to attend from a range of viable options.
Levinson warns that choice here should not be understood in terms
of an educational marketplace where a service is provided to
consumers, a mistake many liberals intuitively make which is
itself illiberal because it ranks market over political and
social values. Rather, choice should be among student-centered,
not consumer-driven schools. Choice should be an active process
guided by free advice from academic professionals and not
constrained by school-dictated admissions criteria. Levinson
adds that no potential option should be a school which reflects a
“fundamental or socially divisive” (p. 157)
conception of the good, for fear that such a school would fail to
fulfill the requirements of commonality or detachment.
Therefore, religious schools, as purveyors of divisive visions of
the good life, could not fulfill her liberal ideal. She does
not, however, deny the functioning of private schools, but does
suggest that they would require more extensive regulation to
ensure that they meet liberal educational aims. She does a
superb job of complicating the school choice debate through the
use of conflicting empirical data and pinpointing theoretical
differences between opposing positions. This discussion is
timely in the United States given fresh evidence from test
programs such as that in Cleveland and concerns with national
assessment following President George W. Bush’s recent
education mandates. It is also relevant to U.S. concerns with
illiberal and intolerant teachings occurring in some fundamental
religious schools. Although the discussion partially fulfills
her aim of making liberal theory tenable through responding to
empirical issues that affect it, its inclusion does not fit
comfortably with the flow of the rest of her more theoretical
argument.
One liberal education demand which may not sit
well with many readers is that the aims of autonomy-developing
liberal education should be constitutionally enshrined, thereby
obligating the state to achieve them, though limiting public
debate regarding them. Fixing educational aims in this way is a
bold assertion, as I am sure Levinson is well aware. Such a
suggestion limits the liberal ideal of public deliberation which
won over many liberals following its expression by John Rawls a
decade ago (1993). While she admits that debate about the
elements of autonomy and the curriculum most successful for its
achievement could continue following constitutional appointment,
I am concerned about the publicly perceived futility of such
debates. The populous may feel that their opinions are trivial
in comparison to the will of a state already made more powerful
through Levinson’s assigning it even more control.
Throughout the book, she echoes and confirms many of the
democratic points of the more widely read Gutmann, but, more true
to liberalism, she argues that democratic deliberation, though
important, should never be able to override the essential aims of
education. Republican controlled government and growing numbers
of libertarians make talk of more state controlled schooling
unlikely in America. Though seemingly untimely given its release
in 1999 at the end of democratic presidential reign, perhaps the
book is even more pertinent to liberals who feel more compelled
now than ever to ensure that autonomy-based aims are being met in
schools free from false-consciousness. And to this I toast
Levinson and those encouraged to join her.
In her concluding remarks, Levinson insightfully
recognizes that legislation regarding and constitutional
inscription of the aims of liberal education are not enough to
achieve her ideal. Political, legal, and cultural reforms are
required. Rigorous teacher training in the importance and
methods of developing autonomy is necessary, amongst other
things. Most of all, an “autonomy-valuing liberal
culture” (p. 165) is essential. To this end, she concludes
by offering a challenge to citizens who have been swayed by her
argument, to act on the very dynamic notion of liberalism which
she has articulated. Her well-organized, clear arguments which
require only minor understanding of philosophic methodology are
likely to convince many already liberally persuaded readers, as
well as some skeptics, to heed her call. Her tone carries
conviction, which is not lost even when she admirably admits
uncertainties or potential objections to her views, and this may
convince even her more staunch critics to at least
collaboratively join the discussion.
References
Callan, E. (1988). Autonomy and Schooling. Montreal:
McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Galston, W. (1991). Liberal Purposes. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Galston, W. (2002). Liberal Pluralism. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Gutmann, A. (1987). Democratic Education. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Levinson, M. (1999). The Demands of Liberal
Education. New York: Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. (1993). Political Liberalism. New York:
Columbia University Press.
About the reviewer
Sarah M. McGough is a doctoral student in philosophy of
education in the department of Educational Policy Studies at the
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Her interests
revolve around feminism, pragmatism, political theory, and
ancient philosophy.
| |
No comments:
Post a Comment