Titone, Connie. (2004). Gender equality in the
philosophy of education: Catharine Macaulay’s forgotten
contribution. New York: Peter Lang Publishing.
Pp. viii + 173
$29.95 ISBN 0-8204-5174-6
Reviewed by Jiwon Kim and A. G. Rud
Purdue University
May 12, 2005
Connie Titone explores the
educational thought of a largely forgotten figure, Catharine
Macaulay (1731-1791), a contemporary of Jean-Jacques Rousseau,
and best known as a political historian of eighteenth-century
England. Titone seeks to understand why Macaulay’s work on
education, seemingly so revolutionary and pioneering, has been
marginalized and nearly forgotten. Titone, like Nel Noddings,
Maxine Greene, Jane Roland Martin, and many others, strives to
continually add women to the historical conversation about
education, where their voices have been overlooked or
forgotten.
The book has two aims. First, Titone initiates an
“informed conversation with contemporary readers about
Macaulay’s work on education within its own historical
context (p. 13).” Second, we are reminded of the
“potentially powerful connection” between beliefs
about human and divine Nature, and the impact of these on a
philosophy of education, in particular, on curriculum,
educational policies and practices (p. 13).
Titone works to correct a history of educational
thought that has been unchallenged for years. Macaulay is central
to an understanding of the discussion of education at the time of
Rousseau. Many philosophy of education courses assign his
Emile as a canonical text. Titone shows how Macaulay both
adopts, develops, and counters Rousseau. It is a
discussion well worth examining, given the dominance of Rousseau,
and his subsequent influence on Pestalozzi, Froebel, Montessori,
Dewey, and others.
We are both philosophers of
education, and Rud has taught texts that do not challenge
Rousseau’s views on women’s education. Rousseau is
well known for prescribing that Sophie, Emile’s helpmate
and companion, be dutiful and an accessory for Emile, whose
education he writes about with more interest. Rousseau states
that Sophie should be both subservient and pleasing to Emile, and
such sentiments strike our modern ears as unrelentingly sexist.
Titone is right in stating that the “true quarrel that
existed at the time” (p. 4) is largely unknown to both
scholars and students. Compounding this oversight is that
feminist philosophy of education is a relatively recent
accomplishment.
Titone is concerned that many of us see
philosophy of education as containing two parallel developments,
one male, and longer, and the other female, shorter, and
derivative, or worse, veiled or absent. Titone examines
Macaulay’s Letters on Education with Observations on
Religious and Metaphysical Subjects (1790), where she
articulated her philosophy of education. Macaulay’s book
integrates her metaphysical beliefs and epistemological view with
pedagogy and practice, so that it is difficult for a modern
reader to understand fully the connections. Titone, however,
remains convinced that Macaulay’s work was underestimated
and continues to be so today.
The most important aspect of Letters on
Education demonstrates the visionary and cohesive nature of
Macaulay’s ideas about gender and education. The ideas can
be broken down into two connected parts. First, Macaulay
reconceptualizes human nature. In Part I of Letters on
Education, she understands that human nature is separate and
distinct from the manifest set of properties of boys and girls
observed in society. Therefore, the attributes, as well as the
behavior, of both boys and girls are redefined, enlarged, and
refocused in order for each to enjoy a closer match between what
is possible by nature and what it seen in conduct. She says that
men and women, striving for a reflection of the totality of
humanness, can both be more divine.
This does not merely mean that women can be more
like men if educated with them. For example, Macaulay insists on
boys’ nascent emotional and moral equality with girls, and
demands that young boys receive an education commensurate with
the development of this aspect of their humanness. In Part III of
Letters on Education, Macaulay gives a thorough
explanation of her metaphysical views on human nature and the
divine mind. Such a concept of mind comes from her interpretation
of the nature of God, the one perfect divine Mind. In other
words, she argues that education should help both genders
approach the nature of God. She uses the terms,
“justice,” “equity,” and
“reason” on the other hand and
“benevolence,” “sympathy,” and
“tenderness” on the other to describe two types of
attributes of the deity (p. 142). She sees both types as elements
of God, and therefore as naturally occurring and equally valuable
in human nature – what one could call “a
masculo-feminine Nature” (p. 10). Herein is the problem of
current education preventing both boys and girls from fulfilling
their humanness and potential by distinguishing the nature of
women from the nature of men.
This insight is naturally connected to her other
key idea, equal education for both genders. Titone sees the canon
of philosophy of education dominated by works by men such as
Plato’s The Republic, John Locke’s Some
Thoughts Concerning Education, and Jean Jacques
Rousseau’s Emile. Rousseau, for example, believes
that male and female human beings possess two different and
distinct human natures, which are predisposed toward the
development of specific characteristics required to fulfill
socially defined gender roles.
Macaulay’s work on education, published
only a few years after Rousseau’s Emile,
convincingly refutes Rousseau’s simplistic and conventional
views on gender and education. She claims that the ultimate goal
of formally educating young people is to produce an educated
person who attains the character, morals, and knowledge possible
for individuals of both genders. She hypothesizes that the
character of human is formed from the influence of education. The
aims and purpose of education that Macaulay suggests are removing
the “echo of the public voice” (p. 42) and
“cultivating virtues” (p. 45).
Macaulay presents the idea of benevolence as the
supreme virtue. There are similarities here with Nel
Noddings’s well known discussion of “caring,”
and Carol Gilligan’s attention to the particular qualities
of women’s moral reasoning, which requires attention to
feelings, care, response, and relation rather than to merely
justice and issues concerning the quality of life. Beyond this
discussion, Macaulay claims that those virtues should be taught
to not only girls but also boys for the individual fulfillment of
their
"Divine mind and potentials, as there is equal
rationality in both, and this is not gendered." (p. 27)
Chapter 5 gives the working details of her
philosophy, namely to think independently and act benevolently.
Like Rousseau, she believed that childhood should unfold and
develop naturally, with children occupied by amusement and play
early on, and not learning to read until later, and then to take
part in a classical education, heavy on reading. Macaulay states
that “(A)ll curricular decisions should be made…with
an eye toward a particular character formation” (p. 98).
Her ambitious curriculum develops thinking and the power of
judgment. Like Locke, Macaulay gave primacy to moral development
over rational knowledge.
The keystone of moral development for Macaulay
was benevolence. For Macaulay, benevolence meant being actively
involved rather than just passively refraining from harm (p.
134). Benevolence must temper reason; otherwise, reason would be
misused. And too, benevolence involves self care, rather than
simply sacrifice for others. This is a hard thing for teachers
and many other people to enact, especially teachers, who give to
others continuously often at peril to their own mental and
physical health. In the final part of the book, Titone
investigates how Macaulay can be of use to teacher education.
Titone sees that ethical maturity, as part of a transcendent view
of education, should be a central part of the development of a
teacher.
This book will be useful to us as we teach the
cultural foundations of education to hundreds of undergraduates
each year. Teaching Rousseau’s Emile is always difficult,
as many students wonder about the context of his extreme views on
gendered education. Connie Titone’s book deepens
one’s understanding of the beginnings of modern educational
philosophy, and brings a forgotten figure forward to rejoin the
conversation.
About the Reviewers
Jiwon Kim is a doctoral
student in philosophy of education at Purdue University. Her
areas of interest include aesthetic education and moral
development. A. G. Rud is associate professor of
educational studies at Purdue University. A philosopher of
education, he edits the journal Education and Culture
(http://digitalfocus.thepress.purdue.edu/eandc/).
No comments:
Post a Comment