Saturday, February 1, 2025

Raschke, Carl A. (2002). The Digital Revolution and the Coming of the Postmodern University Reviewed by Charalambos Vrasidas and Michalinos Zembylas, Intercollege, Nicosia, Cyprus

 

Raschke, Carl A. (2002). The Digital Revolution and the Coming of the Postmodern University. New York: Routledge/Falmer.

Pp. 129
$19.95 (Paper)     ISBN 0415369843

Reviewed by Charalambos Vrasidas &
    Michalinos Zembylas
Intercollege
Nicosia, Cyprus

January 15, 2004

Technology has often been cited as the major driving force behind innovation in higher education and for educational reform in a variety of contexts. Carl Raschke, in The Digital Revolution and the Coming of the Postmodern University, advances some interesting arguments and makes some intriguing observations regarding the status of higher education and the impact of technology on the university. One of his major arguments is that technology and the Internet are having a major impact on education and that they are bound to change the traditional university into what is called the “hyperuniversity,” which in no way resembles the contemporary physical university. As indicated in the title, the arguments set forth in the book come through a postmodernist lens. However, the book lacks the solid evidence to warrant the author’s assertions and to explain how technology and distance education are changing education and traditional schooling as we know it.

The book is divided into nine chapters. The author begins the first chapter “Higher education and the postmodern condition” with the popular quote by French philosopher Jean Baudrillard: “The university is in ruins.” The “postmodern condition” (a Lyotardian expression that is mentioned in this chapter but is not discussed until much later in Chapter 7) is the condition of living in an age in which the all boundaries are fluid, all hierarchies and principles are questioned, and “grand meta-narratives” are held in suspicion. In modernist times, according to Raschke, universities have traditionally been known as the gatekeepers of knowledge. In a postmodern age, the author argues, this will change and the traditional classroom, as we know it, will become obsolete. Teachers used to be the deliverers of a body of knowledge; but now according to the “postmodern prototype,” the concept of a “body of knowledge” does not exist. Citing Deleuze and Guattari, the author argues that knowledge is like “a body without organs,” constantly changing in shape and form. The postmodern university is characterized by a new space: a “knowledge space” — a space that is shaped by the affordances of information and communication technologies. This space shares the nature of a “rhizome” (another term that the author introduces from Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus). In other words, there is no beginning and no end.

Raschke, Chair of the Department of Religious Studies at the University of Denver, argues that we are experiencing “the third knowledge revolution” and as a result we have “the coming of the hyperuniversity.” The rapid expansion of digital technologies has led to the third knowledge revolution. The first knowledge revolution came with the invention of language and the second with the invention of writing. Raschke argues that:

… the coming of so-called “computer mediated communications” that rely on digitized representations that can be disseminated easily and cheaply … —the technical description of what is conventionally known as the “the internet” — are rapidly and ineluctably reshaping our prototypes of what it means to “know” something. (p. 15)

Based on this view, everyone with access to the Internet can be a part of the knowledge space and the communities formed online. Such developments will shift the emphasis from diplomas, degrees, and courses to accreditation of knowledge gained at the workplace and competency based exams. Anyone can study independently online, complete exams, and submit work to receive accreditation. This point of view is held by several other scholars, and it is indeed a valid observation. Anyone with access to the Internet will have opportunities to learn that are independent of place and time.

Several points Raschke makes stand out as important for those interested in how higher education might be affected by these radical changes in technology. Readers are likely to find the book more helpful with respect to describing these changes and celebrating the advantages of the inevitable reform of higher education. However, the book is less helpful in pointing out how current structures in higher education limit the influence of the technological revolution that Raschke celebrates.

The text will disappoint readers who want to find evidence for its claims. One of the limitations of the book is that often the author makes unsubstantiated arguments. For example, at one point he argues that “the learning styles and orientation of the primary college customer are swinging 180 degrees because of the online revolution” (p. 19). There is no evidence in the research literature that “learning styles” are indeed changing. Indeed, teenagers now use the internet frequently and definitely are more technologically savvy than their parents, but that does not mean that within 10 years—since the invention of the internet—humans have experienced a “180 degree change” in learning styles, something that took thousands of years to develop in the first place. Also, in Chapter 3, Raschke argues that research shows that students learn more and faster in the online classroom. To say the least, research on the effectiveness of technology-mediated education and online education is inconclusive (Clark, 2001; Phipps & Merisotis, 1999). A review of hundreds of comparison studies of face-to-face and technology mediated education showed no significant difference in outcomes (Russell, 1999; Twigg, 2001).

In a discussion of the Western Governors University (www.wgu.edu), the author commits another fallacy by arguing the following: “The elimination of ‘contact hours’ and ‘seat time’ as the measure of academic progress, which the WGU foresees, will inevitably compel students to take more responsibility for their education, not less” (p. 20). The illusion that all students placed in a situation in which they will have to take greater responsibility for their education will do so is fundamentally flawed. Unfortunately, the author here shows a lack of understanding of the field of distance education. Most of the research in this field shows that only those students with characteristics such as internal locus of control and high self-regulatory skills are more likely to succeed in a distance education setting (McIsacc & Gunawardena, 1996). Those who cannot take charge of their own learning are likely to drop out. Unless students are provided with the support and skills needed, merely offering them distance education courses will not make them more responsible nor raise their level of skill.

On page 21 (Chapter 2), the author presents a table comparing the traditional knowledge paradigm with the emerging revolution. Although some of the observations are correct, some others are not. For example, the author argues that under the emerging knowledge revolution, the knowledge space that is created is more democratic whereas the traditional paradigm is more aristocratic. Such arguments, praising the democratic nature of the new knowledge revolution and the hyperuniversity, are common throughout the book. Again, the author seems to ignore a whole line of criticism that technologies and the online environment are not ipso facto more democratic (Hawisher & Selfe, 2000; Noble, 1998; Zembylas, Vrasidas, & McIsaac, 2002). One has to acknowledge that online education has several advantages and offers opportunities that are often not available to a large number of people. However, the frequent overly optimistic claims about technology and online education and their contribution to a more democratic world are problematic to say the least. Fabos and Young (1999) argued that we should be skeptical of the fact that “just as telecommunications technology is credited with promoting multiculturalism, it has also been blamed for increasing existing inequalities on a broader scale” (p. 233-234). It is disappointing that the author does not address the issue how exactly the Internet can promote social justice and democracy when the gap between the “have” and the “have-nots” is constantly growing (Lelliot et al., 2000). Comments such as “digital learning is the true bulwark of a global democracy” or “the worldwide use of the new digital communications is steadily growing, even among the so called electronic ‘have-nots’” (p. x) sound simplistic and unfounded.

The book provides other examples of simplistic points. For instance, the position that “In the long haul it is about the dissolution of structures and the true freedom of the mind, a freedom that was impossible in the ‘age of education.’” (p. 61, added emphasis). What exactly is this “true freedom” and how can one achieve it given some postmodernist claims that such a thing does not really exist? Foucault, in particular, in the three volumes of The History of Sexuality argued for a view of power so pervasive that there is no space left for an individual to look for a “true freedom.” All aspects of an individual’s life are subject to disciplinary formation, in Foucault’s view; the very experience of being a subject is an outcome of discursive practices. Any claims about “true freedom” especially in a postmodern context—one which the author aspires to use in his book—are problematic. Furthermore, the author makes the argument that “Our answer to how we can reform the university, henceforth, may be disarmingly straightforward: ‘collaborative groups plus digitization’” (p. 60). If it were only so simple! Although the author may want to be somewhat playful here and emphasize the importance of collaborative groups and e-learning, educational research and theory in the last two decades have shown that there are no simple formulas when it comes to the design and implementation of e-learning (Vrasidas & Glass, 2002).

Also, in our view one of the most flawed analogies that Raschke proposes is that “distance education is to education what mobile homes are to homes” (p. 24). Distance education grew initially from the need for certain people to obtain an education. These were people who the traditional education system failed to serve. However, the assumption that traditional education is “the model” for all kinds of contents, contexts, goals, teachers and learners is unconvincing. Certain learners benefit more from traditional education; others benefit more from distance education. Therefore, the argument that traditional face-to-face education “will remain the dream of parents for their children” is highly problematic and reintroduces a dichotomy between face-to-face education and distance education that we assume the “postmodernist” spirit of this book tries to “deconstruct.”

Another issue that leaves many more questions than answers is the author’s effort to compare “Hegelian thinking” to “digital thinking” (pp. 47, 74 and 76). While it is interesting to make such an attempt, the lack of development of this idea leaves one wondering how Hegelian thought is compatible with postmodernist thought. The author himself recognizes that “All metaphysical systems of representation throughout Western history, from Aristotle to Hegel, have rested on the notion that there were certain conceptual anchors,” as opposed to “postmodern philosophy” which “is characterized by a refusal to ground what we know in certain unshakable ‘positions’” (p. 74). How can Hegel’s insistence on Absolute Knowing be matched with the postmodern refusal of the absolute? Given that the author frames digital thinking within a postmodern context, it is hard to understand the purpose of this comparison. The author alludes to the social and historical process of Hegelian thinking (p. 47) but does not make explicit its possible connections to postmodern thinking and most importantly to the question “So what?”

Finally, in Chapter 5, the author discusses five archetypes and places more emphasis on the transactive archetype of teaching and learning. One needs to acknowledge that the idea of education as a transaction, is not new, but something that was proposed by several philosophers. In particular, Dewey (1938) argued that education is based on the interaction of an individual’s external and internal conditions. Interaction and the situation during which one experiences the world cannot be separated because the context of interaction is provided by the situation. He pointed out that, “An experience is always what it is because of a transaction taking place between an individual and what, at the time, constitutes his environment....” (p. 43, added emphasis) The idea of transaction suggests the intersubjectivity between the individual herself, other people, and her surrounding environment. This transactional nature of education has also been discussed by several scholars (Chen, 2001; Garrison, 2000; Vrasidas & Glass, 2002). Furthermore, the author’s attempt to “sum up” Dewey’s approach “in a few simple propositions” (p. 31) runs the danger of misrepresenting some of Dewey’s ideas, if evidence is not provided regarding where these ideas are coming from. The three propositions on p. 31, standing there as they do without context or explication, may be attributed to a number of pedagogues, philosophers and psychologists including Skinner, Tyler and Bloom’s learning for mastery model! For example, consider the references to “task-defined,” “goal-oriented,” learning, and the “feedback loop.”

This book is not the end of the story, of course, but it is an attempt to engage some critical issues that will be on center stage for this new century. That alone and the author’s commitment to meaningful change make the book useful for those concerned with the future of higher education.

References

Burbules, N., & Torres, C. A. (Eds.). (2000). Globalization and education: Critical perspectives. New York: Routledge.

Castells, M. (1996). The rise of the network society. Oxford: Blackwell.

Chen, Y. J. (2001). Dimensions of transactional distance in the World Wide Web learning environment: A factor analysis. British Journal of Educational Technology, 32(4), 459-470.

Clark, R. E., Ed. (2001). Learning from media: Arguments, analysis, and evidence. Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing, Inc.

Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Fabos, B., & Young, M. D. (1999). Telecommunications in the classroom: Rhetoric versus reality.Review of Educational Research, 69(3), 217-259.

Garrison, R. (2000). Theoretical challenges for distance education in the 21st century: A shift from structural to transactional issues. International Review of Research in Open and Distance Learning, 1(1). Retrieved on March 20, 2002 from http://www.irrodl.org/content/v1.1/garrison.pdf.

Hawisher, G. E., & Selfe, C. L. (2000). Testing the claims. In G. E. Hawisher & C. L. Selfe (Eds.), Global literacies and the World-Wide-Web (pp. 1-18). London: Routledge.

Lelliott, A., Pendlebury, S., & Enslin, P. (2000) Promises of access and inclusion: Online education in Africa. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 34, 41-52.

Levy, P. (1997). Collective intelligence: Mankind’s emerging world in cyberspace. Cambridge, MA: Perseus Books.

McIsaac, M. S., & Gunawardena, C. N. (1996). Distance Education. In D. H. Jonassen (Ed.), Handbook of Research for Educational Communications and Technology (pp. 403-437). New York: Simon & Shuster Macmillan.

Noble, D. D. (1998). The regime of technology in education. In Beyer, L. E. &Apple, M. W. (Ed.), The curriculum: Problems, politics, and possibilities (pp. 267-283). Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

Phipps R. & Merisotis J. (1999). What's the difference? A review of contemporary research on the effectiveness of distance learning in higher education. Institute for Higher Education Policy at the behest of the American Federation of Teachers and National Education Association.

Russel, T. L. (1999). The no significant difference phenomenon. Retrived on January 7, 2004 from http://teleeducation.nb.ca/nosignificantdifference/.

Twigg, C.A. (2001). Innovations in Online Learning: Moving Beyond No Significant Difference. Center for Academic Transformation, Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute.

Vrasidas, C., & Glass, G. V. (2002). A conceptual framework for studying distance education. In Vrasidas, C. & Glass, G. V. (Ed.), Current Perspectives on Applied Information Technologies. Volume I: Distance Education and Distributed Learning (pp. 31-56). Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing, Inc.

Zembylas, M., Vrasidas, C., & McIsaac, M. S. (2002). Of nomads, polyglots, and global villagers: Globalization, information technologies, and critical education online. In Vrasidas, C. &Glass, G. V. (Ed.), Current Perspectives on Applied Information Technologies. Volume I: Distance Education and Distributed Learning (pp. 201-223). Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publishing, Inc.

About the Reviewers

Charalambos Vrasidas is Associate Professor of Learning Technologies and Head of the Department of Education at Intercollege, Cyprus. His research interests include distance education, technology-mediated interaction, and evaluation of educational technologies.

Michalinos Zembylas is Associate Professor at Intercollege, Cyprus, and adjunct professor of teacher education at Michigan State University. His research interests are in the area of emotions in teaching and learning science and technology, science and technology studies, curriculum theory, and philosophy of education.

 

No comments:

Post a Comment