Saturday, February 1, 2025

Callan, Eamonn. (2004). Creating Citizens: Political Education and Liberal Democracy and Feinberg, Walter. (1999). Common Schools/Uncommon Identities: National Unity and Cultural Differences. Reviewed by Thomas F. Green, Syracuse University

 

Callan, Eamonn. (2004). Creating Citizens: Political Education and Liberal Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

272 pp.
$27.50 (Paper)     ISBN 0-19-927019-8

Feinberg, Walter. (1999). Common Schools/Uncommon Identities: National Unity and Cultural Differences. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

280 pp.
$42.50 (Cloth)     ISBN 0-300-07422-0

Reviewed by Thomas F. Green
Syracuse University

March 9, 2004

The world is changing. In what ways, we do not know and cannot clearly see. We have only the faintest vision, but we harbor nonetheless an accompanying suspicion that the changes underway are truly foundational. It is as though we live “between the times,” convinced that is, that the past offers inadequate guidance and that our visions of the future are too insubstantial to “bet the farm on.” Is this anything more than a quite normal situation, something we see with the passage of every generation? Youth are always inclined to be too critical of their predecessors and insufficiently suspicious of their own utopian dreams.

These two books must surely rank among the best of a growing number concerned with the educational formation of citizens in a pluralistic or multi-cultural society. Feinberg proposes to forge what he calls “principled reasons for a common education,” in an age when our understanding of cultural differences poses awkward questions as to whether there is a clear place for “the common school” and, if there is, then what kind of place and what kind of school it might be. The question nags as to where, or even whether, in the face of such multiplicity, we can cultivate the unity of a multi-cultural nation and whether the school can be the instrument of that. His eyes are fixed upon a difference, carefully drawn, between pluralism and multi-culturalism, and upon the need for unity somewhere as the basis of anything like a nation or a nation-state. (Note 1)

What Feinberg means by “reasons” and by “public” or “principled” reasons, will be recognized by many as simply the expansive ideals to which we often appeal in thinking about the education of a public — such ideals as equal opportunity, freedom of association, and the mantras of individual growth. As a way of talking about reasons, this struck me, at first, as a rather odd usage likely to produce confusion among readers. Such things as equal opportunity and freedom of association — whatever one wishes to call them — are not, by themselves, reasons in any sense familiar to moral and political philosophers. They do not have the formal precision of what are usually called “moral principles.” On the other hand, there is a certain loose sense in which this way of speaking is appropriate, especially to the ends that Feinberg has set for himself, namely to say something sensible about these problems to school boards, teachers, and parents. Such ideals, or “ideas,” do provide a kind of matrix for arguments of educational policy and public participation in a liberal tradition. They do delimit what will count as relevant in discussions of policy and practice in the educational enterprise. Thus, they provide reasons in the same way that “being competitive in international markets” currently provides reasons for all kinds of educational sense and nonsense. Such ideals do not provide “principles” or “reasons” quite so much as they forge standards of relevance. One might say that they are “molecular ideas” to which anyone engaged in rational public discussion will have to genuflect. To the question “Why should we do this or that?” in the schools, it is always relevant, if not always true, to argue that doing this or that contributes to the personal growth of students, or to more equal opportu­nity, or that it preserves our freedom of association as a people. In that sense, these ideals stand as the font of reasons of a sort more familiar philosophically.

On the surface at least, the problem that Callan sets for himself is different. It is to spell out the principles (in a more conventional sense of “principles”) needed to vindicate the legitimacy of a liberal political order existing under conditions of pluralism, and in particular to spell out what appear to be the elements of a political morality adequate for the educational formation of citizens.

Many readers will recognize Callan’s discussion as belonging to the growing body of work flowing from John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice and from his subsequent Political Liberalism. As Callan sees it, a major difference between these two volumes can be found in a contrast between a kind of ethical liberalism, on the one hand, in which political coercion is legitimated by some comprehensive moral doctrine universally accepted and a kind of political liberalism, on the other hand, in which agreement on some comprehensive moral doctrine is unnecessary. Universal acceptance of any comprehensive ethical doctrine is an immensely remote possibility in a pluralistic or multi-cultural society, and that fact poses a dilemma for any society pretending to be an association of free, self-governing human beings. In any society whose legitimate coercive powers rest upon some prevailing moral doctrine, there will always be persons living under conditions of felt coercion, because no such “doctrine” will elicit universal consent. Faced with this reality, Rawls frames a kind of political liberalism in which coercive legitimacy is derived from the presence of what might be called “an overlapping consensus” on principles of justice among adherents to the variety of ethical views present in a society of reasonable pluralism.

But what is this “overlapping consensus”? What does such a metaphor describe? The idea’s attraction lies in the presumed neutrality of such a consensus amid contending doctrines, but its difficulty arises from the fact that at least according to Callan, it can’t turn out to be neutral, at least among all possible contending views. Instead of an agreement of sorts, it will turn out to be simply a modus vivendi, an agreement on a kind of “no-man’s land” lacking any genuine moral content of its own. At least that is the claim that Callan and others have directed against Rawls’ formulation of political liberalism. And that lack of any moral content of its own is precisely why such a solution fails, at least as Callan sees it.

Such a modus vivendi, if that is what the idea of “overlapping consensus” amounts to, is forced to carry too heavy a burden. It resembles too much a simple truce, and when trust among human beings decomposes into truce, then any remaining ties that might unite are likely to rest entirely upon the self-interests of the parties to the truce. In fact, it is unlikely that any ties can survive the decay of human relations from trust to truce. At best, a truce offers agreements simply to “cease and desist” for the moment. It is a fragile agreement among combatants not to be at each other’s throats, at least for the moment; and such agreements are unlikely to gain any lofty moral status even though “for the moment” turns out to be a long time indeed, reaching even across generations. Truce does not add up to peace, much less a settled civic order. Or so the argument goes.

Rawls conjectures that in time a truce will “morph” into something more lasting because the force of habit will cover over the fragile tissue of accustomed practices with something like a layer of enforceable, or if not enforceable then at least constraining, usage. So he claims, in effect, that truce is enough to start with. Experience endorses his expectation, perhaps even more than the contrary conviction that such long held fragile agreements most certainly will fail. Yet, even if the expectation could be adequately grounded, that from a truce will emerge something morally more satisfying, still it remains unclear what philosophical work, if any, can be made to rest upon such empirical estimates of probabilities.

Instead of framing the mere grounds of a truce, the principles of cohabitation, to say nothing of cooperation, in any “overlapping consensus,” must somehow take on the force of strong social norms, and strong norms, wherever acquired, carry with them moral authority of sufficient strength, even in public deliberation, to outweigh considerations of mere self interest. So to acquire the norms of some “overlapping consensus” is to acquire moral norms of a quite specific sort. That is why such an overlapping consensus, as it turns out, does and must have particular moral or ethical content. That it might be neutral as among the differing conceptions of a good life in a society of reasonable pluralism, turns out to be an ignis fatuus, a mere “swamp light” that retreats whenever we approach, and yet is so beguiling and so successful in fixing our attention that we fail to note how far astray, in the meantime, we have been led by it. A mere truce will never develop into a stable political order with some constitutive political morality if it rests simply upon the shifting sands of self-interest or group identity. Can’t you hear Hobbes muttering in the background?

These inadequacies in the notion of an “overlapping consensus” at least insofar as they stem from its presumed moral neutrality, are wonderfully exposed when Callan turns to map the details of liberal principles. This, he does again and again by means of narrative and marvelously sensitive description. In his opening pages, for example, he draws our attention immediately to the image of a society in which political life is simply moribund, a society affluent and just in its distribution of wealth, one in which rights, as we think of them have the force of law; but in which when it comes to elections, or, political participation of any sort, even public debate on the basics of their joint lives, people remain simply unengaged. Though such a social order resembles our own, one could hardly describe it as a “civic order.” Indeed, after reflection, it may be difficult even to imagine such essentially uninvolved persons as complete human beings. There is something morally empty in the account of such a life.

From this example we learn quickly and vividly that by “citizens” Callan intends not simply the passive residents of some well-regulated social order. “Citizen” refers not to a status, but to a way of life among other citizens, a way of life moreover, of sufficient clarity and exercised with sufficient skill to offer adjudication, of a sort, among different ways of life. To be a citizen, as Callan sees it, is to be engaged with others in a joint project. He explores this point again and again and others kin to it through rich, and sensitive descriptive accounts of how those principles look when incarnate in ourselves and in our neighbors and in this way he shows us what is lost in their absence. Indeed, the recurrence of such morally serious and perceptive writing, in my judgment, is the major strength of Callan’s book. In this respect, it is a book that, I believe, is astonishingly successful. He doesn’t stop at setting out the bare outlines of principles needed to form citizens as though such a step could provide adequate educational guidance. Instead, he portrays what it would look like were we actually to stumble upon a member of the species that we call “citizen” and know the specimen for what it is.

Consider, as further illustration, his approach to the idea of moral autonomy, that flinty, bloodless rational conception upon which proponents of liberal political life rely so heavily. Here is an idea that comes laden with philosophical credentials from almost every liberal tradition. Even so, one is inclined to think of it as an idea entirely without any clear exemplars anywhere in the real world. Where is one to find a truly autonomous person? What does such a person look like? Are we to search for one whose thinking is genuinely independent, whose conduct is guided entirely by self-legislated rational considerations? In the real world, there never was and, luckily, never will be such a person. Anyone who is only that kind of independent, rational, self-legislating being, is unlikely to be a good neighbor, a generous companion, a compassionate or nurturing parent, a caring mentor. Such an autonomous being is exceedingly hard to find. In short, the problem with this central notion of liberal theory — this idea of moral autonomy — is not its admirable emphasis on the rational, but its blindness to the human need for dependence and interdependence, and the prominence of such a need not merely in the mature being, but, perhaps even essentially, in the growing infant, child, and youth. Being a teacher, parent, guide — these are roles that virtually define for us what it means to intervene in the lives of others in ways that save us from having to depend upon the frail powers of individuals to figure out the moral world entirely on their own. No teacher, certainly no parent, would risk it. None should.

Such an account of “moral autonomy,” you say, is a caricature. And you are right. Even so, it is a caricature rooted in reality and raised here for its own methodological point. About the notion of autonomy, one wants to ask, as one should ask of any philosophical construction, just what empirical reality, what aspect of our moral experience is supposed to be explicated or captured by it? (Call up the imagine of Henry David Thoreau, that scion of a pencil-manufac­turing-family, to many the model of moral independence, in his cabin at Walden Pond with his pencils and paper and his books. Was there ever a person more autonomous yet more attached more indebted to a tradition and more devoted to its preservation? Hardly any of us make moral decisions as autonomous persons and nobody arrives at their moral understanding entirely on their own. Why then does autonomy continue to play so large a role in discussions of moral education? Here is one place (there are others) where Callan’s capacity for sensitive moral writing comes marvelously into play.

The idea of autonomy takes on flesh and blood only when juxtaposed to its intended opposition. To what condition should we contrast such presumed autonomy? That is the crucial question. And the answer is that autonomy is to be understood by its opposition to, among other things, what Callan calls “moral servility.” What drives the intuition and hence drives Callan’s argument, I believe, is not that autonomy is so essential to the moral armament of citizens, but that moral servility is so offensive to anything that we could honestly describe as “citizen.” In this way Callan not only gives concrete meaning to the idea of autonomy, but at the same time positions us to grasp the larger import of a host of arguments scattered throughout the text including, for example, a reconsideration of Mozert v. Hawkins, for it will be apparent to many that whatever plaintiffs complaints in that case, their central aim was to validate and protect their power to shape their children in their own image with as little outside interference as possible. Their aim, in short, was to produce what Callan means by “moral servility,” clearly something to be resisted.

There are other moral ideas that, like the idea of “autonomy,” gather meaning not in relation to some good to be promoted, but in opposition to some condition to be resisted, not in relation to some picture of justice, but in response to the presence and pain of injustice. We are creatures that take deep offense, for example, at the very idea of persons forced to remain captive to demeaning conditions not of their own making or of their own election (in slavery for instance), circumstances in which their powers are stifled. In such settings, human flourishing seems not merely hindered or simply neglected, but willfully forbidden or defeated. We are inclined to the view that such persons deserve to receive, if not some guarantee of exit, then at least some assistance, in the struggle to escape from their condition, if they will to do so. This is the senti­ment shaping not only our notion of autonomy, but also our commitment to equality of educa­tional opportunity generally and to a host of other moral sentiments that can be fashioned into what Feinberg calls “principled reasons.”

It will no doubt appear to some that this emphasis on injustice as opposed to justice, is trivial since justice and injustice are polar terms of a sort, simple opposites, each defined by the other. Such a perspective, however, on the straightforward opposition of justice and injustice will mislead us, and if carried very far, will mislead us very far indeed. Justice and injustice are not in simple opposition, morally speaking. There are relations, like friendship, and many ties within the family, in which injustice may be forbidden, but in which any strict adherence to justice would be declared irrelevant. Insist on receiving justice from and on giving justice to your friends and soon you will have no friends. Yet these are the surroundings in which injustice is most transparently forbidden.

Indeed, of the two — justice and injustice — injustice is the more fundamental to our moral reasoning. It might seem too much to say that this lack of reciprocity in the logical status of justice and injustice awards priority to injustice. Yet, it does exactly that, and rightly so. It renders the recognition of injustice prior to the search for justice, at least in the order of learning and becoming, if not in the order of being. “Priority” is perhaps too strong a word. It might be a mistake to use it. Yet it could not be a large mistake because — to consider a single token of the notion — the law develops, and always has, by observing something like the priority of injustice. (Note 2) Action in a court of law, as in a legislature, begins always with claims of injustice. One must have not only standing to sue, but cause to sue and this cause to sue must consist not simply of a defensible complaint but some actual harm. Even the Norman kings recognized it. One could appeal to the King’s conscience provided one could shout within reach of hearing, “A wrong has been done!” The same reality has long been recognized in the principle that any society, if it will be a free society, can legitimately control entrance to it, but not exit from it. “The restraint of entry serves to protect the liberty and welfare, the politics and culture, of a group of people committed to one another and to their common life. But the restraint of exit replaces commitment with coercion. So far as the coerced members are concerned there is no longer a community worth defending.” (Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice: (Basic Books, NY, 1983) p. 39.) Immigration and emigration are not morally reciprocal. Neither are justice and injustice.

It is well to be reminded from time to time of the circumstances out of which both the idea and the institutions of a liberal polity emerged. They grew out of the need to find some exit, some escape from nearly two hundred years of religious wars. The need was to escape from a world in which pious certainties on all sides led only to combat. (Note 3) The aspiration was for something much more modest than justice. The point to note in this experience is that our principles of association are fashioned and defended not out of a quest — or even a need — for positive philosophical constructions of justice so much as in response to known and transparent evils and to our estimates of the probable risks that such evils as may once have been surmount-ed will return to plague us. The condition of justice is likely to remain obscure despite all our efforts at reaching clarity and however rich the collection of precedent. Injustice, on the other hand, will announce its presence with utter transparency. Justice is embodied in principles and thus is general, but injustice is felt in pain, and is thus particular. It is from our sense of injustice that we come to forge our standards of justice. Says the judgment of conscience, “I may not know what justice is, but I know that cannot be it.” Such a judgment is more easily delivered by ordinary men and women than will be any appeal to some positive principle of justice to be taught and designed to govern in some class of cases.

The idea at hand, is that our moral concepts, insofar as they have to do with the education of citizens, are derived less from applying the rules of justice or fairness and more from confronting specific cases of injustice. It is the look, the taste, the smell of injustice that sends us on the unending task of forging arrangements of a free and democratic society and of educating a people to assume the authentic office of citizen in such an order. Nor is this perspective rooted in some Manichean nightmare of eternal conflict between good and evil. It is rooted simply in an attentive account of how human affairs actually proceed under arrangements appropriate to a liberal social order.

By his attention to the details of cases and to the boundaries of complaint, Callan positions us well to reconsider not only the details of Mozert, but a large range of other cases including, for example, the complaints of the dissenters in Yoder that children of the Amish were given no voice before the court. It seemed to those dissenters more than a tad unjust not even to have asked what they think or what may be their aspirations. On the whole, should parents be left at liberty to shape the education of their children? Of course they should. But that liberty is not without limit. Nor should anyone suppose that simply because parental powers are justly constrained by the collective, it follows that the powers of the collective are unlimited. Injustices arise from both sides. If we can deny parents the right to educate their children in moral servi­tude, then we can also guard against them providing an education in sedition. From the fact that parents do not have sole authority in the education of their children, it does not follow that they have none at all nor does it follow that we must tolerate their inclination to neglect the education of their children even if it turns to total neglect. The education of his children may either be neglected by one’s neighbor or become his sole concern, but, in neither case, can it ever be solely his concern.

It is in exploring the collisions of these intersecting claims, I believe, that Callan’s discus­sion is strongest, whether in exploring, as he does, the limits of parental interests, the boundaries of State interests, the limits of religious toleration, or the moral boundaries of civic participation. The arrangements essential to a civic order in a liberal society, whether multi-cultural or not, are simply those offering assurance that the cries of injustice are never stifled, the search for remedies never aborted. And about those arrangements, two things must be evident — first that really fundamental issues cannot be permanently resolved. Every resolution frames the terms of the next distress and thus initiates the quest for the next adjustment. And secondly, the arrange­ments essential for such temporary adjustments are simply those under which a constantly changing political life might be carried on. They are the arrangements, in short, of a polity, not a morality. And that being so, we find ourselves oddly enough, back in the neighborhood of a truce.

It is important to our grasp of these two books to note that neither contains any sustained discussion of the nature of politics. One needn’t count this fact as defect. Yet, one will surely find in it a powerful clue to what these books are about. Insofar as politics is aimed at framing policy, it could be viewed merely as a people’s way of changing their minds, their accustomed way of saying of some familiar social practices “Oh no! We didn’t mean that.” Insofar as a polity is the structure by which we aim to tame internecine conflict converting it into family squabbles, then politics can be viewed as the periodic renewal of a familiar truce. And finally, insofar as politics is an activity turned upon itself, that is, aimed at reformulating the terms of its own conduct, then it can be understood as an effort to reframe the polity itself.

These formulations raise difficult questions as to what relation there can be between being a good citizen and being a good man or woman. Formulate your list of civic virtues and the question may remain whether they include any moral or intellectual virtues at all. I think it practically certain that some of the moral and many of the civic virtues will have to be included. The crucial point, however, is to note that the list will differ depending on whether you start with an image of politics or whether you start with an image of morality. I suspect that both of these authors begin with a vision of a morally good community instead of a vision rooted in the nature of democratic politics. Hence, they risk advancing goals for civic education more lofty than a good political order requires and perhaps even in excess of what a decent moral view of life can legitimately be expected to recommend. But ponder the matter with care.

Set these books side by side and one’s first impression may be that Feinberg’s is by far the more “densely textured.” On second or third inspection, however, that reaction must be tempered. It arises, initially I think, from Feinberg’s central concern that schools not merely accommodate cultural and ethnic diversity or merely allow it as plain fact, but that schooling be aimed at developing a mutuality among persons of diverse origins and differing dimensions of self-identity at the same time rejecting the dominance of any one cultural group. That is why his discussion seems to confront problems of the educational process more than Callan’s. This impression, however, is misleading. It is created because of his focus on the formation or preservation of self-identity, group identity, and national membership. But when, he turns to consider the details of this education, in the chapter on “Citizenship Education and the Multi-Cultural Ideal,” detail is pretty much neglected and the discussion is conducted at a fairly high level of abstraction.

In that Chapter, Feinberg is prompted to raise the question whether “the liberal multi-cultural nation can be an ethical community?” and he observes, that such a community requires more than simply an understanding of abstract rules. (Pg. 209) He says that “citizenship educa­tion in a multicultural society must have a specific moral content, and it must require complex conceptual skills and concrete moral commitments” of a sort that parents and local communities alone may not have sufficient reason to develop and hence argues strongly for the existence of a public school system that attends to their development.” (206-7) (So much for the adequacy of a mere modus vivendi.) It is these skills and commitments that provide the content for a common education. Central among them, according to Feinberg, are the skills of cultural respect and more than that, cultural competence and cultural understanding.

At this point — the ultimate point in Feinberg’s analysis — several doubts need to be voiced as caution against any too facile adoption of these analytic terms. First, the idea of a political community as a moral community is among the most dangerous aspirations of any people and especially when that political association is constituted and acts in response to cultural and ethnic identities. These are terms that sound very like those that produced the vicious divisions from which the very idea of a liberal order was meant to offer rescue. For more recent versions, one need only recall such names as Bosnia and Kosovo and, to another generation, “The Third Reich.” One should not suppose for a moment that Feinberg has any such thing in mind. Indeed, he is quite clear-headed that “in a multicultural society, one goal of citizenship education is to stabilize a personal, social, and political habitat…conducive to the maintenance and reproduction of a variety of group and cultural formations,” a habitat that supports “many different concep­tions of the good life”(p. 203-4). That is simply part of what we mean by the phrase “multi-cultural.” No such society can be unitary in the sense in which Bosnia, Kosovo, The Third Reich aimed to become. Then too, it is important for Feinberg’s case to note that what he calls “cultural respect,” much more even than “cultural competence” is precisely what seems always to be the first thing overwhelmed when the search is on for a polity that is also a moral community. The fact seems to offer historical vindication of Feinberg‘s claim that advancing something like “cultural respect” is an essential of civic education.

However, the conceptual and human boundaries of anything we call “respect” are terribly obscure. Just as the principles of a liberal order offered response to the need for something short of justice, so also the conditions of a multicultural society must rest upon a standard that falls considerably short of mutual respect. The fact is that any political order of a multicultural society, must be able to hold among persons when mutual respect does not abound. It must hold not just between friends, but also where enmity exists. Respect, in one sense of the term, is too high a standard. One is entitled to suppose that even in the Biblical Peaceable Kingdom when lion and lamb lie down together — even there — no doubt the lion will retain his conviction that all that regal demeanor is justly bestowed right where it is, and thus, will continue to look upon the lamb not with respect, but with plain contempt, at most, with carefully measured restraint. And on his side, the lamb will no doubt remain resolute in his suspicion of any neighbor harboring so natural an inclination to rule, a suspicion triggered especially by the approach of dinner time. What is needed, even in the peaceable kingdom, is not respect, much less mutual respect, but simply that, come morning, the lamb is able to rise again.

As far as I can tell, the only exegesis of “respect” that Feinberg offers is the claim that we must “respect the rights of those who are different from ourselves”(212). This is a standard of respect as forbearance. It certainly falls short of anything we could call respect in the sense of esteem. Respect as forbearance is a mere pittance of what a moral community requires for its foundations. Yet, it may be just the thing for the formation of a viable polity. It does not mean that I must esteem those who are different, or be fond of them. Nor does it even imply that I should respect the difference in the sense of valuing it. To respect the rights of those who are different from ourselves does not imply that I must like the ways in which they are different, or admire them, or even that I must approve of their being different. To say that I respect my neighbor’s property means simply that I will do it no harm, will not invade it, not intrude upon it unless invited. Respect of this sort is simply the same asured restraint that the lion offers to the lamb. Add up the circumstances included in this description and respect comes precious close to being little more than “indifference.” Respect is reached under circumstances where the difference simply doesn’t matter. Such respect falls far short of any positive social tie or moral or civic virtue. It is merely a rule of forbearance. “Respect” understood in this way, is not a term of trust, but of truce. Respect as forbearance is too low a standard to provide moral foundations, and “respect” as esteem, though of solid moral pedigree, is a standard far too lofty to expect of human beings as human beings are known to us, and a standard much higher than any polity requires. And so we find ourselves once more back in the neighborhood of a truce.

It’s enough to make one wonder again, What’s so wrong with a truce? We do well to recall Cicero’s claim in his sequel to Plato’s Republic, that the Republic rests upon a common agree-ment concerning what is good, and James Madison’s contrasting claim that the problem is to devise of way of deciding what to do in the midst of the undoubted fact that we do not agree on what is good. The main objection of those who criticize liberalism for its presumed moral neutrality, boils down, it seems to me, to the simple complaint that liberalism is a view about polity (not morality) according to which no single view of the good life will be allowed to work its way unhindered. The righteous, in particular, will take offense at the notion of a polity in which their undoubted wisdom is hindered in its march toward the moral reform of the world. Yet, instead of saying, “Let us do as much good as we can imagine” principles of a liberal order say simply, “Do as little harm as you can manage.” It is the most fundamental ethical demand of medical practice.

This liberal perspective can be discovered in Feinberg’s treatment. However, he frames the problems of preserving a “common” education in a multicultural nation by terms that seem to me not altogether helpful. He aims to confront the facts of cultural and ethnic identity, and in that respect offers a helpful, balanced, and calmly reasoned account. Such terms, however, are in other respects inappropriate for making explicit the needs of a liberal polity for the education of citizens. The focus on identity is sometimes important, but more often, I think, it is not. There are enormous numbers of persons even in multicultural America who could not claim any identity expressed in such cultural or ethnic terms. Others will claim that whatever their identity, it became apparent to them only after having encountered “the other,” that is, only after having discovered that they are American, for example, because of some incidental habits or marks of demeanor that surfaced only by living among the French, for example or among the “Anglos” in Quebec, or the “Hispanics” in Texas and California. That is when one is likely to discover one’s national identify in the sense of acquired habits and dispositions of conduct, thought, and mannerisms. I have my Irish and English ancestry, but “the Irish” remain a source of endless amazement and wonder to me as do many other peculiar and strange peoples, and the English figure in my make-up — if that is what identity is — mostly as the source of wit, law, and great literature. Neither, I think, figure at all in anything I would call cultural identity, much less my “identity.”

That is my ancestry, but it is no part of my memory or identity. On the other hand a peculiar frontier ethos rooted in the prairie is another story I could tell stemming partly from life among the Amerind — mostly Lakota, Oglala, and Omaha. It constitutes none of my ancestry but much of my social memory and thus some part of my identity. Life on the prairie instills deep respect for the modest life and for the transience of achievement together with a deep suspicion of pretence of all sorts, but especially the pretence of a “city critter” (a phrase in those quarters uttered always with a sneer) or anyone stemming from “beyond the Mississippi,” i.e., “the East.” Identity matters educationally primarily in respect to groups, and primarily groups that are marginalized and suffering the injustice of some oppression. If we search for principles engaged in the educational formation of citizens for a multicultural society and if we seek to unfold their pedagogical consequences, then surely we need to look elsewhere than to “identity” for the formation of a viable public, national or otherwise. Three quick points are worthy of note.

The first is to note that there are at least two ways in which law can be construed as valid in guiding the limits of public action and defining the boundaries of what can be admitted to public debate within a liberal order. The first is that if law in general is to be regarded as valid, i.e., as binding, then it must be properly, that is, legally enacted. The second is that law, so enacted, be framed so as to allow a plausible story to be told about it within each of the various groups of a multicultural society. That is to say, law is not valid simply because it is validly made and made at the center of such a society. It must also be interpretable in a local story about our common life in communities of belief and custom at some distance from the center. Law is not only nomos, but also narrative. (Note 4) The need for a suitable narrative is one expression of historical consciousness, but it need not be ethnic or cultural. The law must enable a story that can be told by the Pennsylvania Dutch as well as the Philadelphia Quaker, the New England mechanic and so forth. This is the political equivalent of the old insight that a political order, if it is genuinely political and not simply tyrannical, must aspire to gain the consent of the governed.

Secondly, we are unlikely to find principles to guide the conduct of education in a multicultural society without a developed view of politics that enables us to mark a difference between the requirements of morality and the requirements of being a political actor. It should not take as given the claim that only a good man or woman can be a good citizen much less a good leader of a free people.

So what are those essential dispositions needed to exercise the office of citizen? I have tried to set them forth elsewhere (Note 5) and so will not elaborate here. They can be gathered briefly in two clusters; (1) The skills of public speech, and (2) the dispositions of a political actor.

First among the skills of public speech is the capacity to hear the speech of “the other” as candidate for one’s own; and companion to this, the capacity to tell one’s own story in ways that can be heard by others. And, of course, if this is to happen, then the polity must include the means for persons of one self-consciousness to speak to others of another consciousness. Feinberg is well aware of this requirement for public speech, or at least, one side of it. He says, “The way to teach students to engage in public discourse is not to require them to mute their own unique cultural voice but to teach them how to have that voice heard by others who may not agree with it.” (p 225).

Second among the skills of public speech must be the ability to go beyond the level of wants and desires to advance public claims about public affairs. That people want a certain thing, a certain liberty, a certain program of education, a certain tax benefit, does not in itself place any claim upon the rest of us to grant it. The distance between “I want X” and “X is a good thing for us to do” is the distance between the pleadings of petulant children and the discussions of adult citizens. That members of my “group” see things this way rather than that, is something that ought to be said and heard. But because some ethnic or cultural group sees things this way or that creates no claim for special attention upon others in the society. There is no legitimacy in the mere fact of difference. The skills of public speech include the capacity to speak of the world as one knows it and to hear the voice of the other as candidate for one’s own speech

Here there is implicit already an extensive educational agenda for education in a multi­cultural society. Especially when added to the dispositions of a political actor in such a polity, these dispositions do not differ much from those that are essential in any liberal polity. Those added virtues or dispositions of the political actor would have to include the difficulty of acquiring a kind of rational patience and forbearance, by which I mean, enough sense of prudence not to act foolishly, the modesty to suppose that in all likelihood one may be wrong in one’s favored course of action recommended for others, and a reluctance to impose one’s own sense of the good life on anyone else. I can think of no better summation of these requirements, nor can I imagine that there can be a better summary formulation than to be found in the concluding remarks of Abraham Lincoln’s Second Inaugural:

"With malice toward none, with charity for all, with firmness in the right as God gives us to see the right, let us strive on to finish the work we are in, to bind up the nation's wounds, to care for him who shall have borne the battle and for his widow and his orphan, to do all which may achieve and cherish a just and lasting peace among ourselves and with all nations."

Notes

1. And a good thing it is to mark these distinctions. Feinberg is very clear-headed that talk of a multicultural nation and a multicultural state presupposes a strong unity of a sort that talk of a multicultural society does not. “To neglect the nation as a bridge between different cutural groups,” he says, “divorces the state from its communal base and leaves the idea of the nation inchoate and impotent.” (p. 212)

2. Indeed, this presumed priority of injustice has been developed into a comprehensive approach to jurisprudence. Professor Edmund Cahn made it the central theme of his account of the structure of law. See The Sense of Injustice (New York, New York University Press, 1949), The Moral Decision (Bloomington, University of Indiana Press, 1955), The Predicament of Democratic Man, (New York, The MacMillan Company 1961).

This apparent “priority” may also be a peculiar mark of Anglo-American legal traditions. Continental law tends to specify what is required in conduct, thus taking form in legal codes, saying, in effect, “You must do this.” Anglo-American law, however, tends to spell out what is forbidden, thus avoiding codes and turning to a more fluid path of statute and custom, saying in effect, “Beyond these things that are forbidden, you may do whatever you wish.” The one says, “You must do what is required”; the other, “You may do whatever is not forbidden.”

3. See Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe, edited by Edmund Leites, (Cambridge University Press, 1988); the opening essay is "Governing Conduct" by James Tully pp. 12-71. “Therefore, how does one distinguish an erring conscience from a true one? The radical puritan's answer is that those with a regenerate conscience do not err because the grace or spirit of God moves their assent from within and secondly, they know that they are regenerate or elect by virtue of an inner assurance or grace. The conscience is thus sovereign and cannot be subordinated to any authority or authoritative external criteria. As Catholic opponents were inclined to say, these radical Protestants had set up their conscience as a new pope,” in every little soul a little pope installed. (p. 19)

4. See Robert M. Cover, “Nomos and Narrative, The Supreme Court, 1982 Term” (Harvard Law Review, 1983, 97, p. 4) for a detailed exploration of the virtues and liabilities of such a perspective. I am not so much concerned here with the adequacy of such a view, but with the necessity of allowing it to appear in discussions of most of the legal controversies that figure in the conflicts that Callan so ably pursues.

5. See Thomas F. Green, Voices: The Educational Formation of Conscience, (Notre Dame, Notre Dame University Press, 1999) esp. Chapters 7 and 8.

About the Reviewer

Thomas F. Green
Philosopher in Residence on Pompey Hill
Box 100 Pompey Hill, New York 13138
Emeritus Professor, Syracuse University

Tom Green is Professor Emeritus, Philosophy and Education, Syracuse University. From 1980 until his retirement in 1993, he was Margaret Slocum Professor of Education. He was a faculty member in the School of Education from 1964. He has earned degrees from the University of Nebraska and a PhD in philosophy from Cornell University. He is author of six books—one more than Moses—and nearly a hundred articles on teaching, educational policy, school finance, moral and theological education and educational and social forecasting. From 1967-73, he was founding Director or Co-Director of the Educational Policy Research Center at Syracuse, a federally funded center for the study of education policy and social forecasting. He was President of the Philosophy of Education Society, 1975-76. Since, 1979, he has been officer or member of the National Academy of Education, an elected body of outstanding American scholars and educational leaders. His books include Predicting the Behavior of the Educational System, (Syracuse University Press, 1980); Work, Leisure, and the American Schools, (New York, Random House, 1970); The Activities of Teaching, (New York, McGraw Hill, 1971); Voices: The Educational Formation of Consicence (Notre Dame University Press, 1999. He is currently engaged in work on a companion volume in philosophy of education and pedagogy: Walls: Education in Communities of Text and Liturgy.
 

No comments:

Post a Comment