Ernest, Paul (1998). Social Constructivism as a
Philosophy of Mathematics. Albany, NY: State
University of New York Press.
Pp. xiv + 315
ISBN 0-7914-3588-1 $59.50
Reviewed by James A. Telese
University of Texas, Brownsville
June 15, 1998
Paul Ernest makes an important contribution to the
philosophy of mathematics by arguing that traditional
epistemology has not ensured the infallibility of
mathematical knowledge. His thesis is that the genesis of
mathematical knowledge is a human endeavor, a process in
which historical origins and social context play important
roles. Throughout the book where appropriate, Ernest
provides a point-counterpoint approach when presenting his
ideas, as he anticipates and responds to possible
objections.
His argument is centered around two "maverick"
philosophies established by Lakatos and Wittgenstein.
Lakatos's view regarding mathematical proofs and
Wittgenstein's "language games," are woven together into a
coherent view of mathematics called social constructivism.
Social constructivism, which includes intuitionism, is an
extension of constructivism and other philosophies, such as
fallibilism. Readers who are unfamiliar with certain
aspects of the philosophy of mathematics, such as
absolutism, formalism, and constructivism have no need to
avoid the book because the author presents these various
views clearly enough as he lays the foundation for his own
brand of social constructivism. This review will focus on
Ernest’s social constructivism and its sources in Lakatos
and Wittgenstein.
Ernest believes that mathematical knowledge is
influenced by human activity and contends that mathematical
knowledge is situated within and grows out of a community
composed of individual mathematicians. The key word is
"community." An emblematic quote would be the following:
"all knowledge is rooted in basic human knowledge and is
thus connected by a shared foundation ... human agreement is
the ultimate arbiter of what counts as justified knowledge"
(p.48). The implication is that since mathematical
knowledge is a product of the social nature of the
mathematical community, then the development of mathematical
knowledge cannot occur without human activity.
It is the role of the philosophy of mathematics "to
reflect on, and give an account of, the nature of
mathematics" (p. 51). He offers six criteria for judging
the adequacy of a philosophy of mathematics:
- mathematical knowledge and the role of proof
- critical evaluation of theories
- objects of mathematics
- applications
- activities of mathematicians both past and present
- how mathematical knowledge is passed on from one
generation to the next
Ernest develops his view through a thorough explication
of these criteria, which are used to support the idea that
the historical origins and social context of mathematics
should be admitted as proper concerns of the philosophy of
mathematics.
Criteria one and three represent the focus of
traditional epistemology and ontology. Criterion two is
included because it is concerned with the usual form of
mathematical knowledge. And through criteria four and five,
Ernest extends the traditional boundaries of the philosophy
of mathematics and helps legitimize the idea that
mathematics is related to other areas of human knowledge.
Criteria six relates to mathematics education and is
concerned with how mathematical knowledge passes from one
generation to the next, how it is learned, and the
dialectical relationship between individuals and existing
knowledge. Ernest’s account thus includes external issues
such as the history, genesis and practice of mathematics,
along with internal issues such as the justification of
mathematical knowledge itself.
Ernest prepares the reader by offering a thorough
critique of a kind of absolutism that has been the dominant
view of mathematical knowledge and the traditional
philosophy of mathematics. Absolutism makes two basic
assumptions: 1) mathematics qua knowledge is in principle
separable from other human activities, and 2) mathematical
knowledge and logic are absolutely valid and infallible.
These assumptions mean that, for the absolutist, the truths
of mathematics and logic are absolute and infallible.
However, Ernest’s compelling critique of absolutism
proceeds by establishing that mathematics and logic are
indeed fallible by their very social nature. In a deductive
system such as mathematics, certain established rules and
statements are assumed to be true while "logical rules of
inference preserve truth" (p. 14). In the absolutist view,
axioms are assumed and the rules of inference follow a
formal syntax. For Ernest, though, in the mathematical
community proofs result from a social discourse in which
participants agree to accept or deny particular theories.
The validity of a deductive proof is therefore based on the
"transmission of truth." Ernest establishes that proofs are
outcomes of socially agreed upon sets of rules and
mathematical objects, such as definitions, axioms, and
theorems. Proofs are made up of "deductive logic and
definitions which are used with an assumed set of
mathematical axioms or postulates . . . to infer
mathematical knowledge" (p.3). Hence, proofs--the heart and
soul of the creation of mathematical knowledge--are
themselves socially derived. This claim premises Ernest’s
social constructivist philosophy.
Further support for this proposition is found in Lakatos
and Wittgenstein. The fallibilism of mathematical knowledge
was first addressed by Lakatos in 1978. The underlying
notion is that knowledge, based on human opinion or
judgment, has the possibility of losing its truth or
necessity. Through the door of fallibilism, the author
offers a naturalistic account of mathematics. Ernest's
argument is further strengthened by incorporating
constructivism with intuitionism. He realizes that although
intuitionism is a well established constructivist philosophy
of mathematics, its weakness lies in the fact that axioms
and associated proofs derived from intuition cannot stand
alone in establishing absolute truth based on subjective
beliefs. Consequently, Lakatos incorporates general aspects
of constructivism and fallibilism into a theory where the
standards for rigorous proof in mathematics change and
evolve over time.
As Ernest suggests, a careful analysis of Wittgenstein
is necessary for an understanding of social constructivism.
For Wittgenstein, mathematics is one among many language
games which possess certain features that must be followed
in order to participate, such as rules, behavioral patterns
and linguistic usage. Meaning is thereby established from
social patterns. In order to participate in a language
game, one must accept certain rules in order to apply terms
in social discourse. The rules and form of the game may
change but are learned through participation in the game.
In the mathematical community, agreements regarding the
rules of mathematical proof and establishing theories arise
from a shared language. This suggests that mathematicians
have established guidelines for the verification of proofs.
Depending upon social conditions, the guidelines may change
as a result of a new approach to mathematical proofs. For
example, in the past, proof by computer would have been
unacceptable, but the community has recognized the
legitimacy of computer generated proofs; thus, what counts
as a rigorous proof can change due to particular advances
such as technology.
The language game of mathematics includes informal
mathematical practices as well as formal practices. As in
any language, the syntactic rules are important for
understanding to occur among the participants. The form of
the rules and their acceptance evolve within context-related
linguistic and social practices. Mathematical knowledge is
created in the minds of individual mathematicians,
participating in language games, each of whom
idiosyncratically construct meaning. In this case,
"mathematics is constructed by the mathematician and is not
a preexisting realm that is discovered" (p.75). Aspects of
mathematics that are considered to be inventions include
mathematical propositions, theorems, mathematical concepts,
and the forms mathematical expression may take. The social
nature of mathematics is established by meanings derived
from the context-related linguistic and social practices.
Consequently, mathematical knowledge is founded on human
persuasion and acceptance.
In support of Wittgenstein, Ernest employs Lakatos's
theory of Quasi-Empiricism, which claims that mathematical
knowledge is fallible and corrigible. Mathematical
knowledge, represented by proofs, is considered to be the
outcome of a language game. Ernest elaborates Lakatos's
view of the evolution of mathematical knowledge in terms of
the Logic of Mathematical Discovery (LMD): a cyclic view of
the development of proofs. There are three stages. The
first stage is the called the "beginning" stage where
primitive proofs develop. The second stage is called the
"mid-cycle" where proofs and refutations occur. The third
stage is the labeled "new beginning." During the third
stage, improved conjectures are developed through criticism,
analysis and strengthening of the proof and of the primitive
conjecture, leading to the new conjecture. From this
perspective, proofs grow from a process of conjecture-
refutation-new conjecture.
Proofs develop within the social community of
mathematicians and are considered mathematical knowledge
when they are fully established through a testing process.
The social nature of mathematics is visible when a proof is
presented to a body of mathematicians. The proof is placed
under scrutiny and faced with either acceptance or rejection
if flaws are present in the proof, a new and improved
version is then presented. The cycle continues in a similar
fashion until there is agreement. Mathematical knowledge
is, thus, tentative, continually being tested, and not
necessarily established by rigorous proof alone because the
guiding assumptions are based upon human agreements that are
capable of changing; conjectures, proofs and theories arise
from a communal enterprise that includes both informal
mathematics and the history of mathematics.
Ernest believes that the LMD offers a unified theory of
mathematical development with four functions. He sees the
first function as a philosophical description accounting for
the genesis and justification of mathematical knowledge and
the detailed epistemological pattern of mathematics. The
second function is historical and describes the actual
development of mathematics. A third, a heuristic function
provides guidelines for practicing mathematicians to follow.
The fourth function is related to pedagogy, and describes a
method for teaching mathematics that parallels its
historical development.
The role of informal mathematics is pivotal for both
Lakatos and Ernest. Within the mathematical community,
informal mathematical theories are first established and
then explained through formal means. This process refines
and redefines the mathematical concepts, conjectures, and
proofs that function as a filter for mathematical knowledge-
-a filter that may itself be reformulated in response to the
criticism of the mathematical community. Since it remains
possible that resultant proofs may or may not be successful,
it seems that the potential falsification of formal
mathematics ultimately depends upon the informal
mathematical theories.
The formation of mathematical knowledge thus relies
heavily upon discourse and rhetoric. Ernest contends that
the LMD reflects a dialectical logic of human conversation
and interaction and is therefore a language game with
alternating voices in dialogue. Language is crucial to
social constructivism, as knowledge grows through language
and the shared meanings it makes possible. According to
Ernest, "... the social institution of language . . .
justifies and necessitates the admission of the social into
philosophy at some point or other" (p. 131). Mathematics
has many conventions which are basically social agreements
on definitions, assumptions and rules. Objective knowledge
rests within the social framework due to linguistic rules
and practices. For social constructivism, mathematical
knowledge and logic are epistemologically social phenomena
that includes language, negotiation, conversation and group
acceptance. As a result, "social constructivism accounts
for both the 'objective' and 'subjective' knowledge in
mathematics and describes the mechanisms underlying the
genesis . . . of knowledge socially" (p. 136). So,
objective knowledge in mathematics is taken to be what is
accepted and warranted by the mathematical community. So
the real purpose of proofs is to persuade the mathematical
community to accept certain claims.
Ernest argues further that the transmission of
mathematical knowledge is a key aspect of social
constructivism. There must exist a social context for the
learning of mathematics, and items of mathematical knowledge
differ in significance and meaning depending on that
context. Similarly, learners' knowledge of mathematics is
related to shared social activities. The function of
mathematical symbol systems as semiotic tools must be
socially acquired and mastered if students are to gain
mathematical knowledge and competence. Semiotic tools have
their own rhetorical features and become part of the overall
social constitution and context of the classroom. The
acquisition and use of mathematical knowledge are not
readily detachable from social activities and are often
elicited as a result of an engagement with a specific social
situation. One such situation is the mathematics classroom,
which also has its language games and communally-shared
social forms of life. A problem, however, lies in the fact
that there are significant variations in the rhetorical
demands of teachers in different contexts. For example,
through participation in the high school algebra language
game, beginning algebra students must learn how to use
variables in mathematical sentences with their own syntax
and semantics and represent common language in mathematical
form, use various tools, such as graphs, tables, or
calculators. The language is acquired through shared
meanings.
Ernest views the mathematics classroom as a micro-
community composed of individuals using their personal
knowledge of mathematics and mathematics education for
directing learning conversations, presenting knowledge to
learners, and to participating in a dialectical process of
criticism and warranting others' knowledge claims. The
school context is one part of the creative/reproductive
cycle of mathematics. The other part is the academic
context. In each context, there is action associated with
human activity such as conversation/negotiation and a
textual movement of mathematics, the publication of
mathematical knowledge open to public criticism.
Overall, Ernest’s scholarship is deep and insightful.
It is also wide: he uses the ideas of many other thinkers
such as Dewey, Foucault, and Vygotsky to lend greater
support for his social constructivism. Ernest helpfully
reminds us that mathematics is not independent of social
concerns. External circumstances such as funding for
research, developments in adjacent fields such as
theoretical physics, or technological developments such as
those in numeration and digital computing, have an impact on
problems, solutions, concepts, standards for proof, and the
overall shape of mathematics as a discipline. Mathematics
as a cultural activity is not devoid of human failings. It
cannot develop or evolve without human thoughts, actions,
reactions, acceptances and revisions. Mathematics and
society shape one another, and by recognizing this social
constructivism represents an advance in the philosophy of
mathematics that is, for this reviewer, a welcome departure
from the cold and unyielding nature of the traditional view.
About the Reviewer
Jim Telese
University of Texas, Brownsville
School of Education
80 Fort Brown
Brownsville, TX 78520
|
No comments:
Post a Comment