Nelson, Adam R. (2001). Education and Democracy: The
Meaning of Alexander Meiklejohn 1872-1964. Madison: The
University of Wisconsin Press.
Pp. xix + 416
$34.95 ISBN 0-299-17140-X
Reviewed by Jinting Wu
University of Wisconsin, Madison
August 6, 2006
An important book that rediscovered a rare figure in the
history of American higher education, Adam Nelson’s
Education and Democracy: the Meaning of Alexander Meiklejohn
1872-1964 spans almost a century to delineate the contours of
the life of a man, a real champion of freedom, a philosopher but
not a pragmatist, who set out to discover the meaning of
democracy, who weathered defeats yet never compromised his
aspiration, who took faith in the inestimable virtues of human
spirit, who traveled a difficult path with unshakable optimism,
and who strived for, above anything else, the rejuvenation of a
liberal education and democratic unity.
Books on democratic ideals are many. This one stands out from
the rest because firstly it is a biography of a man who had so
much to contribute to the pursuit of democratic education yet
whose idealism had been unduly dimmed by the boisterous quest for
pragmatism and empiricism. Secondly, unlike many works on
democracy authored by political or social scientists, this book
was written by a historian who is well versed in philosophy and
intellectual history and who is acting fundamentally
democratically through documenting the life of a neglected figure
and bringing diversity to an era of profound intellectual
conversation. What is especially compelling about this book is
its eloquence and grace in illuminating intricacies of
philosophical debates. Precisely because of the intellectual
nature of this biography, this book review will focus its
analysis through an intellectual lens.
Following chronologically the four most significant places in
Meiklejohn’s life—Providence, Amherst, Madison, and
Berkeley—Nelson illustrates the evolution of
Meiklejohn’s intellectual philosophy through his identities
as Dean of Brown University, President of Amherst College,
Director of the Experimental College at UW-Madison, founder of
the San Francisco School of Social Studies for adult education,
and not the least, absolutist interpreter of the First Amendment.
Nelson’s vivid narration and descriptive language renders a
dynamic portrait of Meiklejohn’s career as well as the
visceral experience of his democratic endeavors.
Growing up in a working-class family that actively engaged in
the practice of social and economic cooperation, Meiklejohn
developed early in life an enthusiastic interest in democracy.
College life at Brown solidified his philosophical foundation in
Kantianism that upheld unity of mind and matter and supremacy of
intellectual reasoning. In an age deeply entrenched in empiricism
that downplayed human nature, the belief in the intrinsic
divinity of human mind set Meiklejohn apart from the mainstream
intellectuals and presaged his deep disagreements with Deweyanism
in his later life. Meiklejohn’s academic prominence as well
as personal charisma earned him the much-coveted position of dean
at his alma mater. No sooner had he embarked on this new career
than Meiklejohn set out to foster a democratic community, his
first experiment in the practice of democratic education. He
tested his faith in student self-government and outlined his
theory of democratic education. Despite the mounting criticism
among his colleagues towards campus athletic controversies and
students’ disciplinary problems, Meiklejohn remained firm
in his belief that the institution of democratic education should
teach youth how to abide by moral principles and strive for a
common cause by allowing them to run their own affairs
autonomously.
Departing Brown, Meiklejohn assumed the presidency of Amherst
College to start a new phase of his democratic experiment. He
called for intellectual reconstruction of the stagnating college,
berated its elective system, introduced the idea of student
council to help with college governance, and upheld the critical
intellectual purpose of a liberal education. He set his heart on
curriculum reform and faculty change and ushered in the use of
classic texts to achieve intellectual unity and moral integrity.
Yet his endeavor was severely undermined by the imminence of
World War I. Staunchly opposed to students being enlisted for
war, Meiklejohn invited bitter criticism and found himself in
profound difficulty to keep his liberal college intact. And yet,
he remained true to his ideals that a liberal college must be
set apart from its culture, detached from worldly affairs in
order to be critical and unbiased, and dedicated to the highest
truth, virtue, and democratic ideals. However, Meiklejohn’s
drastic reform and vision of a liberal democratic college did not
appeal to his tradition-bound dogmatic faculty, and the deep
animosity between them caused a turmoil in his professional life
and ended in his dismissal.
Nonetheless, Meiklejohn remained unscathed by the defeat and
pushed forward to spearhead a new experiment at UW-Madison. The
Experimental College, a college within a university, stimulated
intellectual enthusiasm and self-government, created a
residential hall to host students and advisors alike in a
tight-knit community, and used the Great Books curriculum to
teach students how to teach themselves. However, The Experimental
College’s structural isolation from the rest of the
university and emotional schism from the ethos of contemporary
society foretold its early ending. Situating the Experimental
College in its historical context—an age of economic
disintegration, cultural decadence, and spiritual
depletion—Nelson painted an enthralling picture of
Meikejohn’s failing battle to keep moral degradation and
anomie at bay.
Assured of the rectitude of his democratic ideals, Meiklejohn
moved westward and founded an Adult Education School in San
Francisco. Using Socratic teaching and the Great Books, this
community-based democratic education model trained adult workers
in the critical deliberation of common social problems as well as
practical methods of labor organizing. Central to
Meiklejohn’s democratic ideal was the art of thinking
independently yet collectively. In deliberation of controversial
issues, Meiklejohn asserted, teachers could not, and should not,
take neutral positions because they were in their own ways
forming conclusions about these controversies. If Nelson had
taken Meiklejohn’s argument a step further, he probably
would also agree that by pretending political neutrality teachers
commit a moral crime of insincerity and betray the very principle
of democratic teaching.
The termination of his San Francisco School coupled with the
rise of Fascism in Europe and the Japanese bombing of Pearl
Harbor spurred Meiklejohn to explore the role of state authority
in democratic education. Fascinated by the duality of personal
autonomy and state authority, individual freedom and collective
order, Meiklejohn saw state as the primary embodiment and
safeguard of individual rights. Setting himself apart from the
Renaissance rhetoric that human beings were created equal with
inalienable rights, Meiklejohn asserted, rather, these rights
were formless, embryonic and did not exist until the inception of
an authoritative body—the state. The belief that the state
rather than God is the creator of humanity and civilization
encapsulates Meiklejohn’s political and educational
philosophy. His state-centered philosophy invited outrage and
assaults especially from Dewey's followers. However
authoritarian and oppressive his ideology might have seemed,
Meiklejohn did not depart fundamentally from Dewey, for his
state had none of the character of a dictatorship, but
rather it was a collective body of both ethical principles and
effective governance, that is, a moral teacher that synthesizes
different perspectives into solidarity and advances collective
decisions to safeguard individual freedom. It was the
reconciliation of individual freedom and state governance,
however contradictory the two seemed seemed, that Meiklejohn
worked keenly to achieve.
Throughout his professional career, Meiklejohn remained
steadfast in his tireless battle for free speech, which was
epitomized in his absolutist interpretation of the First
Amendment. To Meiklejohn, subscription to political parties,
even those with allegedly subversive purposes such as Communism,
should not be denied individuals, for a climate of suppression
would only jeopardize the integrity of democratic living.
Precisely by allowing free expression of conflicting advocacies
and ideologies would Americans acquire the capacity to think,
decide, and govern themselves cooperatively.
As the name of the book suggests, Nelson intended a comparison
between Meiklejohn and his much more widely known contemporary,
John Dewey, whose work is epitomized in the book Democracy and
Education. While both embraced freedom and a liberal
democratic education, Meiklejohn and Dewey as intellectual rivals
were deeply divided in their philosophies and embarked on vastly
different journeys to achieve democracy. Firstly, they defined
public differently. To Dewey, the public was generated
from numerous personal interests, and therefore, was utilitarian.
Meiklejohn’s public, however, was the outgrowth of
collective reasoning, and therefore, was deeply ethical.
Secondly, while Dewey upheld empiricism and emphasized
experiential learning, Meiklejohn was essentially idealistic and
stressed the Great Books curriculum and the study of classic
texts. While Dewey advocated learning by doing, Meiklejohn saw
great value in meaningful deliberation to achieve moral
integrity. As Deweyan pragmatists relentlessly sought scientific
interpretation of human behaviors, so did Meiklejohn in his
indefatigable striving for the unity between empirical facts and
moral values. Well versed in Kant’s epistemological
idealism, Meiklejohn embraced wholeheartedly the complementarity
of mind and matter and the transcendental power of pure reasoning
in fostering empathetic brotherhood. The debates between
Meiklejohn and Dewey were indeed nuanced and intricate. With
elegance and clarity, Nelson renders the presentation of their
philosophical discourse both penetrating and illuminating.
Bringing education and democracy into sharp focus, Nelson has
wisely called our attention to a symbolic yet controversy-laden
man, who tried tenaciously to settle a dispute concerning the
meaning of democracy, and whose vigor and quality of mind had so
much to teach us in our own search for a democratic and just
society. Meiklejohn dreamed of a world governed by moral
principles, unfettered by prejudice and dogmatism, and above all,
a world of intellectual unity whose members deliberate
independently together. A fervent Kantian believer in the power
of transcendental reasoning, Meiklejohn turned to philosophy for
resilience and elegance at times of trials and tribulations. In
his quest for spirituality, philosophy had done for him what
religion had done for many others: it helped him to achieve
genuine connections between the present and the transcendental,
the trivial and the grand, the physical and the spiritual, and
the individual and the universal. Indeed, the journey Meiklejohn
had chosen was a difficult one; even to this day, the dilemmas
that confronted him continue to plague those who ardently strive
for the rejuvenation of American democracy and liberal
education.
A book of meaningful purpose, carefully researched and
cogently argued, eloquently written, light-heartedly
philosophical and passionate, Adam Nelson’s Education
and Democracy: the Meaning of Alexander Meiklejohn 1872-1964
brings history alive. Readable and vivid, even for readers
outside the academic sphere, this book defies the abstruseness
and aloofness of too much academic writing and has the power of
mounting enthusiasm after the first few glances.
On the other hand, the book sometimes dives, unnecessarily,
too deep into the intellectual debates and contradictions and may
perplex readers who are unacquainted with the convoluted
metaphysical discourse. For instance, Meiklejohn at one point
stated that freedom was prepolitical, for only freedom of speech
and deliberation could bring about collective aspiration and
unity, the very essence of democracy; at another occasion he
asserted that freedom could not exist without the formation of a
state which granted and safeguarded such a right, and therefore
was postpolitical.
The reader might have a legitimate interest in
Meiklejohn’s personal life, yet Nelson’s rendering of
his professional life falls short of satisfying such a query. To
do so will entail an oral history of sorts and require yet
another research project. As Nelson stated at the outset, his
goal, rather than offering a complete chronicle of
Meiklejohn’s life, is to allow Meikeljohn to speak for
himself. In so doing, as well as for putting Meiklejohn into
meaningful conversations with his most prominent protagonist,
John Dewey, Nelson has done well.
About the Reviewer
Jinting Wu
Department of Educational Policy Studies
University of Wisconsin-Madison
1000 Bascom Mall
500 Lincoln Drive
Madison, WI 53706
Copyright is retained by the first or sole author,
who grants right of first publication to the Education Review.
No comments:
Post a Comment