| |
Reviewed by Jon N. Hale April 15, 2008 J. Wesley Null in Peerless Educator: The Life and Work of Isaac Leon Kandel documents and narrates the life of an education scholar, Isaac Kandel, whose prolific and wide range of scholarship is worthy of emulation. Null documents the impressive life of Isaac Kandel, a historical figure who worked in several notable positions, such as a Teacher’s College professor between 1923 and 1946 during the heyday of Progressive Education, a close friend and associate of William Bagley (an earlier biography project of J. Wesley Null), and a scholar who served in an international capacity that helped spawn the field of comparative education. But Null’s project in the Peerless Educator moves beyond the basic descriptive biographical project, for Null rearticulates the perennial debate between “progressive” and “traditional” educational reformers and scholars. In providing the social and political context of Kandel’s rise in academic circles, which occurred on both sides of the Atlantic in New York City and Manchester, England, Null necessarily defines and illustrates the problematic and ever-changing attempts to define Progressivism from the vantage point of a scholar who was divisively anti-Progressive, or a “democratic traditionalist” in Null’s words. In the end, the reader is left with a text with a two-fold purpose to provide a biography but also to redraw the lines between traditional and progressive camps that should make readers rethink their own positions on this debate. In terms of the biography project, Null assumes the approach of an intellectual biographer with “particular attention to [Kandel’s] views on educational philosophy, curriculum, and comparative education” (p. xix). In this regard, the reader comes to know Kandel in the context in which he would develop his educational philosophy. Kandel was born in Romania in 1881, migrated to Manchester, England, in 1885 during the Victorian age in order to live in the largest Jewish community in England, numbering 35,000, to escape the hardships imposed on Eastern European Jewish communities (pp. 25-43). In response to the pervasive “Jewish Question,” Kandel would mediate between the British and Jewish cultures to learn that “assimilation was protection against discrimination” (p. 38). Kandel’s educational experience is very important to understand as well. Kandel attended a British public elementary school during the era that witnessed the proliferation of universal education and consequently internalized the British education ideals of citizenship and non-sectarian Christian morality (p. 42). Kandel later attended the prestigious Manchester Grammar School, which was rooted in Christianity and classical scholarship (p. 46). Despite excelling in a curriculum grounded in the classics, humanities and religion, Kandel was not awarded a scholarship to Oxford or Cambridge and instead attended the University of Manchester in 1899, an institution that oriented itself toward educating males for public service using a non-sectarian curriculum and civic purpose. Kandel received his bachelor’s degree in classics and later received his masters in education at the University of Manchester, at which point he sought to “perpetuate the ancient traditions that he had been studying for fifteen years” (p. 61).
A
classical and moral education would prepare Kandel for his
career. By happenstance, he met William
Chandler Bagley at the University of Jena, Germany, and
decided to move to New York City to study for his PhD at
Teachers College (pp. 79-81). Kandel’s dissertation is
instructive in outlining his general educational philosophy and
scholarship. Kandel’s work focused on German teacher
education and how national ideals shaped a national education
system. He recommended high-quality curriculum teacher education
with a liberal arts focus and criticized rigid bureaucracy and radical
curriculum changes, which were becoming key components of the
burgeoning Progressive movement. (pp. 98-100). Teachers College was also definitive for Kandel because there he met William Heard Kilpatrick and Paul Monroe, both affiliated with educational history. Kilpatrick would serve (more than Dewey) as the Progressive figurehead against which Kandel would write. Monroe would influemce Kandel greatly as a member of his dissertation committee but would crucially recommend Kandel for positions as, first, a research specialist for the Carnegie Foundation in 1914 and later to a professorship appointment at Teachers College in 1923 as part of the International Institute. Beyond this capacity of a Teachers College professor, Kandel would serve in an international capacity, becoming well known in the field as a founder of comparative education. Kandel, for instance, edited the Educational Yearbook, which published essays by leading representative scholars of education from different countries (pp. 141-143). In addition to this important scholarly project, Kandel served on the U.S. Education Mission to Japan that was charged with reporting on Japan’s wartime education system in order to democratize Japanese education (pp. 205-208). Kandel also worked with UNESCO to establish a minimum Fundamental Education for all world citizens, which was to argue that “universal liberal education is a human right” (p. 217). Finally, Kandel returned to head an American Studies program at the University of Manchester until 1950 (p. 238). The more important aspect of this text, however, emerges as
Null pays close historical attention to “[Kandel’s]
life, his thought, and the way in which his views clashed with
the views of others from his time period” (p. xix). Null
makes sure that his project resonates with similar debates today
for “good educational history…must have something to
say about application” (p. xx). The thrust of Null’s
text therefore lies in his positioning of Kandel in the larger
Progressive versus Traditionalist debate. Null interestingly
redefines Progressivism in this text. He rearticulates David
Tyack’s widely accepted administrative and pedagogical
progressive binary. Instead of administrative progressives, Null
proffered the term “systematic progressives,” who, in
Null’s analysis, rejected humanistic liberal curriculum,
encouraged the complete adoption of scientific analysis and
methodology, and sought to produce or “discover” an
efficient system to be applied to American education (p. 132).
Null replaces the notion of pedagogical progressives with
“existentialist progressives,” which are those more
aligned with the Dewey camp that encouraged the incorporation of
behavioral and developmental psychology into teaching. For Null,
the existentialist progressives were known for “worshiping
the wants, needs and desires of children” (p. 133). Null
found that the Progressives commonly placed significant emphasis
on the individual, used “romantic rhetoric”
often with the promise of some type of Utopia. They made
the ideas of progress, efficiency, problem-solving and individual
advancement fundamental in education (p. 135). Furthermore, for
Null, the Progressive movement represented an “attack on
the idea of curriculum itself” (p. 149). Similarly, Null divides the Traditionalist
camp into two components. The “aristocratic
traditionalists” represented the old guard that largely
rejected a liberal, universal education. Null found this camp to
be elitist, gender discriminatory, and reactionary in their
rejection of universal education (p. 136). The second component
is composed of the “democratic traditionalists.”
For Null, Isaac Kandel was a democratic traditionalist. In
general terms, the democratic traditionalist believed in
traditions and advocated universal liberal arts education,
something rejected, according to Null, by the Progressives. Such
traditionalists also incorporated science into their methodology,
but maintained a “larger social and philosophical vision
that puts the common good of humanity at its end” (p.
137). The move to redefine and rearticulate this debate is
crucial for Null, for he sees that this tradition was
marginalized during the early to mid twentieth century, but also
because it represents a tradition that must be reclaimed.
Anticipating the question as to why this idea did not take hold
in educational theory, Null demonstrated that the democratic
traditional project was ignored and marginalized because such an
approach was philosophical in the time when behavioral psychology
and positivist methodology dominated educational theory and
practice. Additionally, this approach would not yield the
simple, “ready made” answers that many demanded (p.
17). Following the democratic traditionalist
framework, Null makes it
clear that teachers should teach a common culture, which he sees
as fundamental for the survival of American democracy. The
curriculum should also espouse “the eternal ideas that have
shaped civilization” in a liberal arts curriculum (pp.
9-10). Moreover, Kandel’s work in comparative education
leads Null to conclude that a focus on international peace is the
only viable long-term approach to problems like terrorism.
Ultimately, education should incorporate Kandel’s goal
“to identify universal principles of humanity
that…should be taught in all countries to all young
citizens” (p. 13). The result would be to implement a core
curriculum grounded in morality. Like Kandel during the
Progressive era of education, Null proposed that educational
theory reject pragmatism and industrialism as ends. Instead,
educators should expand the curriculum to include philosophically
humanist considerations. In the end, ethics and morality are
imperative, yet dangerously lacking components in American
education. Null maintains that contemporary policy needs
“morally engaged, philosophically minded decision makers
who can think long-term, communicate with the general public and
serve the common good” (p. 21). As Null concludes,
“liberal education is a religious ideal that transforms the
inner constitution of a person’s character” (p.
277). In terms of methodology, historical and philosophical
understandings need to be the foundation of teacher education
programs. The contemporary context, Null argues, demands that the
ideas put forth by Kandel be rediscovered and incorporated into
education. While Null’s nuanced typology structures
Kandel’s life and his larger philosophical conflict in an
ordered waywhich helps rearticulate a longstanding debate
in the fieldhis distinction between Progressive and
Traditionalist camps is problematic at times. Null draws
a stark contrast between the two sides that may tacitly serve the
contemporary debate between Diane Ravitch and others rather than
demonstrating valid historical interpretation. The
“progressives,” already a loaded and broadly
encompassing term (which Null acknowledges), are presented at
times as a movement marked by anti-democratic, wholly
individualistic and otherwise explicitly socially harmful
tendencies. The harmful effects of behavioral psychology and an
uncritical acceptance of a scientific positivist
methodology are duly noted, but this should not be used as the
sole criterion to define the Progressive movement. Pedagogical
progressives would use science as just one means to benefit both
the individual and society. Basing historical analysis on
the assumption that the Progressives did not consider the larger
social good leads to some unfounded (and sometimes harsh)
indictments. For instance, at one point it was claimed that
Progressives were “worshiping the wants needs and desires
of children” and succumbing to the use of “romantic
language” (p. 133). The reader is later instructed that
Dewey rejected “truth, beauty and goodness” (p.
196). Worse yet for the American student, the reader is also
informed that the “radical” Progressives, led by
George Counts, espoused an ideology that flirted “with
totalitarian ideologies that rejected equal educational
opportunity” (p. 166). This could also be
problematic if one considers the notion that the Progressive
movement was not the dominant paradigm it
is often allegde to be in the history of education.
Progressivism was not the panacea that some claimed it to be, but
illustrating the Progressive movement in such language only
serves to portray Kandel as a martyr for a righteous cause,
politically establishing the conservative as the victim within
the contemporary debate. Another aspect of Null’s provocative
argument should be noted as well. In an era when many critics
rightfully claim that too many scholars critically describe
without suggesting an alternative course of action, Null suggests
that morality be re-incorporated into the American curriculum,
that a common culture be transmitted in schools, and a core
curriculum be adopted. With the help of a
foreword in Peerless Educator by Diane Ravitch, these
lines are clearly drawn. Null's position is courageous in that it
takes a firm stance, but it is problematic at the same time because
Null’s idea is not fully articulated for those who are
inherently skeptical of notions such as one common culture,
morality, and a core curriculum. The question remains as to whose
culture and morality should be taught and how. Moreover, besides
the safeguard of a moral and common education for all, if
this notion were to be taken seriously by practitioners, how is
it possible to avoid the inherent discrimination and harmful
effects historians have documented in the “moral”
policy of the Native American boarding school movement, for
instance. Moreover, it would need to be demonstrated how a
common culture and curriculum could reflect the socially and
often ideologically diverse nature of American culture.
More is needed to persuade the opposition
if a serious dialogue on a national curriculum is to be held.
In the end, Null has contributed a
well-written text that boldly rearticulates current debates in
education over the nature of the American curriculum and
teacher education programs that should help readers reexamine and
redefine their own positions in this ongoing debate. On these
merits alone, Null’s Peerless Educator is a
worthwhile and important text. In terms of
biography, Null has contributed a well-documented biography that is
indicative of the high-quality scholarship that can be found in
the history of education. Null’s claim in the introduction
to be writing an intellectual biography is modest, for he
incorporates the social, political, personal, and cultural
contexts of Kandel’s life that makes this biography a much
more comprehensive biography that Null himself claims.
Null’s Peerless Educator may not end the debate over
the aims of American education, but it is an important
contribution to the debate and a model illustration of historical
scholarship. About the Reviewer Jon N. Hale is a doctoral student in the Department of
Educational Policy Studies at the University of Illinois at
Urbana-Champaign. His specialization is in the history of
education and his specific research interests include critical
theories in education, educational reform, and democratic
education. His MA thesis examines the history of the Mississippi
Freedom Schools in 1964. He has presented his research at
conferences sponsored by the American Educational Research
Association, History of Education Society, Southern History of
Education Society, Midwestern History of Education Society, and
American Educational Studies Association. |
Sunday, June 1, 2025
Null, J. Wesley. (2007). Peerless Educator: The Life and Work of Isaac Leon Kandel. Reviewed by Jon N. Hale, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Janesick, Valerie, J. (2006). <cite>Authentic Assessment Primer</cite>. Reviewed by Kristin Stang, California State University, Fullerton
Education Review. Book reviews in education. School Reform. Accountability. Assessment. Educational Policy. ...
-
Ravitch, Diane. (1996) National Standards in American Education: A Citizen's Guide. Washington: The Brooki...
-
Chomsky, Noam. (2000). Chomsky on MisEducation , (Edited and introduced by Donaldo Macedo). New York: Rowan and...
-
Education Review/Reseñas Educativas/Resenhas Educativas Howe, Kenneth R. (1997) Understanding Equal Educationa...
No comments:
Post a Comment