McCluskey, Neal. (2007) Feds in the Classroom:
How Big Government Corrupts, Cripples, and Compromises
American Education. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield
Publishers.
Pp. 209 $20 ISBN 0742548597
|
Reviewed by Jonathan Anomaly
University of Virginia
June 24, 2008
In Feds in the Classroom Neal McCluskey takes a
critical look at the evolution of federal involvement in American
education from the colonial era through the implementation of
Bush’s brainchild, the No Child Left Behind Act. Often
informative, and occasionally insightful, McCluskey’s book
is nevertheless shot through with an ideological animosity and
rhetorical excess that diminishes its ability to advance the
debate over the proper role of government in education
policy.
McCluskey begins with an engaging overview of early state laws
regulating education. The most memorable is the “Old
Deluder Satan Act” of Massachusetts, which required all
towns with a population of at least fifty to teach their children
basic literacy on the grounds that those who could read the Bible
would be less likely to be misled by the Devil. By the late
nineteenth and early twentieth century, McCluskey argues, state
laws mandating universal education had become a more or less
concealed attempt to assimilate religious and racial minorities
into mainstream American society. Although this is a reasonable
interpretation of history, McCluskey hastily draws the conclusion
that universal education mandates were therefore bad policy. It
seems, however, that we should separate the question of what
motivated some policymakers to mandate universal education, from
the question of whether those policies (of compulsory education
and standardized curricula) were improvements over the
decentralized system of education that had existed before.
The heart of the book is McCluskey’s contention that we
should abolish all federal intervention in education, and
transfer control back to parents and communities. McCluskey
supports his position with three different claims: that federal
intervention is unconstitutional, that it subverts individual
rights, and that it is less effective at achieving its goals than
alternative arrangements that maximize parental choice. At one
point, McCluskey goes as far as to say that “In the
colonial and early national eras,” before the federal
government exercised any control, “American education
worked more or less optimally.” (p. 191) Rather than
evaluating the plausibility of this claim, let us look more
carefully at the three main arguments with which he defends
it.
McCluskey deduces his view that “the federal government
may have no role in schooling” from the Ninth and Tenth
Amendments to the Constitution. The Ninth Amendment, in
particular, reserves any rights and powers not explicitly granted
to the federal government to states and individuals. Since
education is not mentioned in the Constitution, McCluskey infers
that any federal role in education is unconstitutional.
McCluskey may be right about this – a lot depends on
whether we are strict constructionists, and on how we interpret
the “general welfare” clause of the
Constitution. (Article I, Section 8 states that “The
Congress shall have Power To lay and collect Taxes, Duties,
Imposts and Excises, to pay the Debts and provide for the common
Defence and general Welfare of the United States.”) But
important as this debate is, it is essentially about the
interpretation of a document (albeit an extremely important
one). What if the Constitution were amended to permit a federal
role to education policy? McCluskey would presumably still
oppose it, since he believes federal control infringes the moral
rights of those whom it most directly affects: parents and
children.
McCluskey describes prayer in public schools as a “civil
right” and refers to those who are forbidden by federal
policy from reciting prayers in class as a “persecuted
minority group.” (pp. 58-59) Yet it is unclear on
McCluskey’s view whose civil rights are being violated. Is
it the parents or their children? In most of the book McCluskey
views children as belonging to their parents, and describes
federal education mandates as eroding the rights of
parents to choose how and where to educate their
children. But on the issue of school prayer he seems to think
the civil rights of children are violated. This raises
several important questions: First, do children have civil
rights? Second, even if children have such rights, can we
sensibly ascribe genuine religious convictions to children, and
hence conclude that they have a right to practice their religion
freely, or are their religious ideas instead a product of
parental and social indoctrination? Third, even if children have
a civil right to pray to the deity of their choice, should they
be encouraged (or forced) to exercise this right in public
classrooms?
A key premise in McCluskey’s argument that federal
education policy undermines parental rights is that many
controversies over what to teach and how to teach it are
permanent, and that the values that underlie these positions are
incommensurable. Thus, the argument goes, “federalizing
education only raises the scope and stakes of the conflicts to
the federal level, embroiling all Americans in battles over
evolution, religious expression in schools, reading and math
curricula, school uniforms, multiculturalism, and the endless
issues on which all, or even most, people will never
agree.” (p.
140) Yet this is surely an exaggeration: elementary math and
science standards, as well as those for teaching literature and
social studies, are widely agreed upon by educators and
academics. Moreover, giving the federal government some power to
fund schools or establish curricula does not imply that every
dispute should be settled at the federal level. Nevertheless,
McCluskey’s solution to these controversies is to simply
“Let parents use the money the government school system
would have spent on their children to select the schools that
align with their values and educational demands. Let supply and
demand go to work.” (p. 98)
This leads to McCluskey’s final argument against federal
intervention in education—that parents will (on average)
more effectively choose the best education for their children.
This could be achieved by giving parents the ability to choose
the best school for their children, rather than forcing them to
send their kids to the nearest public schools. State financed
vouchers could be allocated to parents to redeem at a school of
their choice. The theoretical benefits of vouchers are well
known: they encourage competition for parental dollars, thereby
giving schools a monetary incentive to hire highly skilled
teachers, improve student performances, and minimize wasteful
bureaucratic expenses. To his credit, McCluskey acknowledges
that the success of vouchers crucially depends on how large they
are – that is, on how much money we give to parents to
choose between schools competing for their dollars. He also
emphasizes that in a voucher program, some taxpayers, especially
childless taxpayers, will be unhappy about paying the costs of
educating other people’s children. (pp. 182-186)
However, McCluskey fails to adequately address some of the
most important concerns over any publicly funded voucher
program. For example, what do we do with schools that fail? In
any competitive market, there are winners and losers, and in
markets for the provision of education the losers may ultimately
be the children who attend failed schools, rather than those who
own or manage failed schools. Perhaps safeguards can be set up
to minimize these problems, but an argument must be made for how
this can be done. More importantly, voucher programs raise the
question of what should be taught at publicly financed schools.
McCluskey’s answer is simple: anything. Let demand
determine supply. This is where McCluskey’s argument is
weakest. While there are clear benefits to increasing parental
choice via vouchers, there may also be significant costs. Unless
similar curricula are required of schools, we may very well end
up with an increase in the social tensions McCluskey wishes to
minimize. In particular, many religious schools may wish to use
their publicly funded vouchers to teach scientifically
discredited theories intended to bolster the faith of students
rather than increase their critical thinking skills or scientific
literacy.
In the end, McCluskey’s book is thought provoking, but
his arguments are inadequately developed, and his solutions are
insufficiently nuanced. They are also couched in the bombastic
language of a conservative ideologue with a deep antipathy for
federal solutions to social problems. Nevertheless,
McCluskey’s book is worth a read, if only to sharpen our
own opinions about the increasing role of the federal government
in American classrooms.
About the Reviewer
Jonathan Anomaly
Jonny Anomaly, a post-doctoral fellow in the philosophy
department at the University of Virginia.
|
No comments:
Post a Comment